Takings Property and Appropriative Water Rights

The Takings Clause of the Fifth Amendment to the United States Constitution provides that “private property [shall not] be taken for public use, without just compensation.”1 While courts and academics have put considerable amounts of effort into discussing the meaning of “taken” or “public use,” they have given far less attention to the phrase “private property.” Notable scholars have provided a set of definitions and frameworks to determine when a particular right qualifies as takings property. However, courts and commentators have yet to define the types of rights that are entitled to constitutional protection with sufficient precision to avoid an inconsistent and inefficient application of the Takings Clause.

This Article argues that, while these definitions of takings property lead to sound and consistent outcomes when applied to traditional rights such as a fee simple absolute or an easement, they produce underwhelming results when tested against less conventional interests. The Article assesses how these frameworks perform with a property interest as elusive as appropriative water rights and provides broader lessons about both takings property and water law. First, it becomes apparent that the existing literature and court opinions have unreasonably sanctified rights in land while decrying other types of interests as non-property by applying inconsistent standards. Second, the analysis of these existing frameworks reveals some critical shortcomings in their design that had not yet been described. To address these issues, this Article proposes a solution that harmonizes some of the central components of existing takings property definitions.

Introduction

The Takings Clause of the Fifth Amendment to the United States Constitution provides that “private property [shall not] be taken for public use, without just compensation.”2 As this language makes abundantly clear, the Takings Clause only applies when “private property” is implicated.3 While a careful examination of this threshold question may not be necessary in some cases, it can be deceptively complicated and outcome determinative in many others.4

What is, then, the meaning of “private property” for takings purposes? Even though no universal answer exists, courts and scholars have been trying to provide a workable definition of takings property for decades.5 To be sure, it is possible to identify easy cases, that is, those where there is ample agreement among scholars. For example, not many academics or courts would question that a fee simple absolute constitutes private property both under the common law and as a matter of state and federal constitutional law.6 Easements are also uniformly viewed as takings property, as confirmed by the Supreme Court in its 2021 opinion, Cedar Point Nursery v. Hassid.7 However, whether these protections extend to interests such as common law water rights, bailments, security interests, trusts, or even taxicab licenses is far less

The scholarly debate on the nature and scope of takings property cannot be untethered from the broader conversation exploring whether there is a definition of constitutional property—which asks this same question, not only focusing on the Takings Clause, but also in the context of the Due Process Clause.8 Three main answers have been proposed in the literature. The first—advanced, for example, by Harvard Law School Professor Maureen Brady—is that Supreme Court precedent does not support the notion that there is a separate definition of property for constitutional purposes.9 In other words, courts should generally decide these cases based on whether a particular right is considered to be property under state common law.10

The second approach is supported by scholars who argue that there is a distinct definition of constitutional property. Stated differently, while nonconstitutional sources—such as state law—may determine the features of a particular right, the right in question will only receive constitutional protection if it meets certain constitutional requirements.11 The third approach, taken by Professor Thomas Merrill in his seminal article, The Landscape of Constitutional Property, proffers not one but three different definitions of constitutional property, each of which applies to a particular context, that is, substantive due process, procedural due process, and takings.12

The scholars endorsing the second approach have had to face the added challenge of providing a workable framework to determine when a particular right will be deemed takings property. Professor John Echeverria, relying on key language provided in Supreme Court precedent, has noted that only two requirements are necessary.13 First, the right must be “specific and identifiable,” and second, it must include “the authority to exclude others from accessing or using it.”14 Professor Merrill, on the other hand, has argued that takings property is present when the right that is being examined presents the following three features: it confers the right to exclude others, it is irrevocable, and it involves “specific assets”—which is a clarification and a considerably more detailed interpretation of the Supreme Court’s “specific and identifiable” requirement.15 Professor James Stern proposes yet another approach, that is, one under which rights that meet the requirements to be considered in rem—as opposed to in personam—are also constitutional property.16 According to the latter scholar, to be deemed in rem, a right must pertain to a “discrete thing,” which is essentially another variation of what the Supreme Court has called “specific and identifiable.”17

This Article argues that existing tests for takings property focus excessively on traditional property rights and present numerous challenges when applied to other, less conventional types of interests.18 This is extremely problematic because the goal of these types of tests should be to allow courts, lawyers, and legal scholars to determine whether a particular right constitutes takings property, not when the answer to this question is obvious, as tends to be the case with land, but in situations in which there could be a reasonable disagreement as to whether the right being analyzed should, in fact, be viewed as takings property.

To expose the shortcomings of these tests, this Article provides an in-depth analysis of a less traditional type of property, that is, water rights. The focus of this analysis is on appropriative rights, a particular type of water right conferred under the common law in western states (i.e., the judge-made law developed in these jurisdictions), which gives priority to water users based on when they acquired the right—a principle often referred to as “first in time, first in right.”19

The overwhelming majority of commentators agree that common law appropriative rights are property under state Whether this conclusion holds true when examining whether appropriative rights are takings property for the purposes of the United States Constitution has been a more contested issue.20 Despite the fact that some scholars have argued vehemently for the opposite view,21 this Article shows that appropriative rights qualify for constitutional protection under the most widely used definitions of takings property, as well as under Supreme Court precedent.22

It is worth highlighting that the fact that common law appropriative rights are takings property does not necessarily mean that any interference with these rights by the government will require compensation. This will only occur in situations in which the right has actually been taken, which involves an entirely separate inquiry focused on the application of the appropriate takings tests.23 Part of this analysis will entail assessing whether any defenses to takings claims would be applicable, especially those that courts and scholars have highlighted as being particularly relevant in the water context.24

Examining whether—and to what extent—appropriative water rights constitute takings property allows this Article to make two broader contributions to the constitutional property literature. First, the scholarly debate on this question reflects a tendency to associate property with rights in land, which, in turn, diminishes the status of other less traditional types of property rights even if they otherwise meet the objective requirements to qualify as such.25 Second, and relatedly, these tests make it very hard to analyze rights that do not relate to land or traditional forms of personal property. These challenges become particularly apparent when one attempts to determine whether the right in question is “specific and identifiable.”26 When asking if water has this particular feature, takings property tests that are almost identical on the surface answer this question very differently, thus revealing some of the flaws in their design.27

This Article proceeds in four parts. Part I explores the scholarly debate surrounding takings property, which focuses on whether this separate category of property exists as well as the requisites that a right must meet in order to be afforded that status. Part II provides an overview of the basic features of water rights and appropriative rights in particular. Part III addresses the question of whether appropriative rights constitute property for takings purposes by first reviewing state court decisions and then applying the definitions of takings property proposed by courts and legal scholars to appropriative rights. In Part IV, this Article explains the broader lessons that can be extracted from the analysis in Part III and how they can be used to address some of the shortcomings in the constitutional property literature.

I. Constitutional and Takings Property

Property rights are typically created and defined by state law.28 This seems both appropriate and convenient given that property rights will typically be enforced by state courts, for example, in tort actions for trespass or conversion.29

However, there are some instances in which a plaintiff may bring an action in court to seek the protection of a property right relying on federal law. For example, the plaintiff’s claim may be based on a right that originates in a federal statute. In Ormet Primary Aluminum Corp. v. Ohio Power Co., two parties claimed to be the rightful holder of an atypical form of property, that is, pollution emission allowances created under a federal statute, the Clean Air Act.30

Another example of a scenario in which a plaintiff relies on federal law to protect a property right is where the claimant invokes the protection afforded by the United States Constitution in connection with a state-created property right. This occurs, for instance, when landowners bring a claim under the Takings Clause of the Fifth Amendment to the United States Constitution, alleging that their property was taken without just compensation.31

In addition to the different bases on which these two types of federal claims are brought—statutory law on the one hand and constitutional on the other—there is an important difference between them. In the first scenario, the plaintiff invokes the protection of the so-called horizontal dimension of property rights, which focuses on the courts’ role in preventing interference by one private actor with the property of another private actor.32 The dispute referenced above, in which the plaintiff’s competitor was attempting to appropriate the plaintiff’s pollution allowances, is an example of this type of interference.33 The vertical dimension of property rights, which is relevant to the second example noted above, protects private parties against governmental interference with their property rights.34

A. Takings Property

This Article focuses on the second dimension of federal adjudication of property rights, which, as noted above, is based on the protections afforded by the Takings Clause of the Fifth Amendment to the United States Constitution and equivalent state constitutional provisions. The Takings Clause provides that “private property [shall not] be taken . . . without just compensation,” but it supplies no further guidance as to what may or may not constitute property for the purposes of this constitutional protection. A critical question this language raises and that is central to this Article is: how should courts make this determination? Or, in other words, how should courts decide what constitutes takings property?35

The Supreme Court has addressed—although not fully answered—this question in a series of cases. In Board of Regents of State Colleges v. Roth, the Court adopted what has been referred to as the positivist approach to defining property.36 In the opinion delivered by Justice Stewart, the Court explained that “[p]roperty interests, of course, are not created by the Constitution. Rather, they are created and their dimensions are defined by existing rules or understandings that stem from an independent source such as state law.”37

In Phillips v. Washington Legal Foundation, the Court evaluated whether the interest in a particular type of lawyer trust account should be considered property under the Takings Clause.38 Justice Rehnquist reiterated that the Constitution does not create property interests, but rather protects those interests that have been created by, again, an independent source of law, which is often to be found in state law.39

The reason why these statements do not completely answer the question of what constitutes property under the Takings Clause is that they are somewhat ambiguous with respect to the role that state law plays in this determination.40 Should we interpret Supreme Court precedent to mean that federal courts should view property as a derivative constitutional right?41 In other words, are state courts’ conclusions as to whether a particular right qualifies as property under state law determinative of whether it should be entitled to protection under the Takings ClauseUnder this second view, there would be a direct constitutional right of property.

Some scholars and courts have claimed that Supreme Court case law seems to support the first option.42 Professor Maureen Brady has noted that “[t]here is nothing remotely close to a definition of federal constitutional property in Supreme Court case law” and added that “a unique federal definition of constitutional property is both a nonobvious proposition and one that would likely be of limited assistance.”43 The Court of Appeals for the Ninth Circuit has adopted this position in numerous cases and has insisted that the question of whether an interest should be viewed as property for the purposes of the Takings Clause should be answered based solely on state law.44

According to Professor Michelman, however, other Supreme Court opinions can be read to support the direct constitutional right to property.45 The Court of Appeals for the First Circuit has also endorsed this interpretation in a case dealing with the issue of whether seniority credits granted to military veterans under a state statute should be considered property under the Takings Clause.46

This second view raises a question that will be examined immediately below: if we read Supreme Court precedent to support the idea that there is a federal definition of property, what is the appropriate test that courts should follow to ascertain whether a federally protected property right is present in a particular case?

B. The Different Definitions of Constitutional Property

In his article, The Landscape of Constitutional Property, Professor Merrill highlights the dangers associated with the positivist approach, or what other scholars have referred to as the “positivist trap.”47 This occurs, according to Merrill, in situations in which federal courts decide to leave to the states the decision of what should be regarded as property for constitutional purposes. In his view, this can lead to state courts adopting too broad a notion of the type of property rights that the Constitution protects or one that is too narrow.48

Of course, those who defend the need to have a unified definition of constitutional property face the challenge of having to articulate what its precise definition should be. Professor Merrill proposes a test under which only those interests that meet three specific requirements will qualify as takings property.49 The relevant question is whether the source of law creating the interest “confer[s] an irrevocable right on the claimant to exclude others from specific assets.”50

Professor James Stern, on the other hand, has suggested an approach that, while similar, relies on the traditional distinction between rights in personam and rights in rem.51 In his view, only in rem rights are property rights.52 In turn, according to this scholar, rights must meet the following two conditions in order to be considered in rem: they must be “centrally concerned with some particular, singular, discrete thing,” and they must be “good against the world.”53 While this “discrete thing” condition could easily be viewed as a mere variation of Merrill’s “specific assets” prong, Stern describes it as the requirement “that the thing be identified with enough specificity to exclude any other candidate or substitute for the thing.”54 The author then adds that rights expressed solely based on quantities, values, or substitutes only represent a simple abstraction instead of the thing itself.55

Other scholars have taken intermediate positions. Professor John Echeverria, for example, has posited that, while Supreme Court precedent seems consistent with the idea that the Takings Clause leaves it to the states to define property interests, this approach has the theoretical danger of allowing states to bypass constitutional protections.56 For example, states that would like to eliminate an existing property right completely without requiring the payment of compensation could simply redefine the interest and characterize it as nonproperty.57 This author, however, notes that, in practice, other Supreme Court precedent forecloses this possibility.58 Other scholars have interpreted this same body of case law to support this view.59

There is a significant level of overlap and agreement among scholars on what a takings property test or definition should look like. Professor Echeverria has noted that the Supreme Court has provided some guidance on the features that a particular interest must present in order to “qualify as property under the Takings Clause.”60 He highlights two requirements that were also addressed, with some important modifications, by Professor Thomas Merrill, that is, the interest must be “specific and identifiable” and it must include “the authority to exclude others from accessing or using it.”61 These factors are also similar to those outlined by Professor Stern.62

These different definitions of takings property are useful in a variety of contexts and are not particularly difficult to apply to traditional property rights, such as rights in land. Easements, for example, fulfill all the necessary requirements to qualify as property both under the common law and for constitutional purposes.63 The real challenge for takings property frameworks and definitions is whether they can be applied with ease and consistency to less conventional rights. Part II lays out the main features of a property interest that will be used later in this Article to assess the consistency and flexibility of these takings property definitions.

II.  Water Rights

Water rights are a particularly good example of a sui generis type of right that can provide very useful insights on the limits and consistency of these takings property frameworks.64 The following discussion will first provide a definition and some general features of water rights and will then delve into the complexities of one of the main doctrines that governs the allocation of water resources in the United States.65

A. Defining Water Rights

Water rights are a somewhat elusive concept Part of the reason why that is the case is that, as will be addressed shortly, there are many different types of water rights.66 At their core, however, water rights typically confer on their holder the ability to use water for, at least, a socially acceptable purpose.67 This can include, for example, depending on the jurisdiction, the right to use the surface of the water for recreation, to divert a certain flow of surface water for manufacturing purposes, or to withdraw groundwater to be used for irrigation.68

This Article focuses on rights to divert surface water. Unlike with groundwater in certain parts of the United States, surface water rights are regarded as a right to use rather than ownership of the water itself.69 For this reason, courts and scholars have often described them as “usufructuary,” meaning, a right held by a person or firm to use water that the state owns.70

Water rights can be broken down into two components. The first, which I will refer to as “present water,” is the power to put to use a specific amount of that resource that has already been diverted.71 Of course, this right to use water is limited in a variety of ways. For example, a water user may only be permitted to use that resource for a particular purpose and on a particular property.72 The second component—“future water”—is the expectation to continue diverting water in the future as long as it is available.73 It is this second part of the right that explains why some water users decide to make certain investments—such as irrigation equipment—in situations where their ability to obtain a return depends on the continued availability of water.74

The right to divert surface water is far from uniform across the United States.75 A key distinction that explains some of these differences is that between riparian and prior appropriation jurisdictions.76 The water allocation system in some states, however, presents features of both doctrines.77 To add to this variability, many jurisdictions have transitioned into so-called permit systems, that is, an approach that relies on a more robust legislative framework and in which government agencies assume a central role in the allocation of water resources.78 The next Section lays out the distinctive features of water rights under prior appropriation.

B. Appropriative Rights

Prior appropriation was developed as a response to the westward expansion of the United States.79 During this process, settlers occupied large western areas that were significantly drier than the East, which created a need for a water allocation doctrine that was suited to this drier climate and the wide variety of water-intensive uses to which these lands were put, such as mining.80 This explains why the states that have adopted prior appropriation are located to the west of the Mississippi River.81

1. Acquiring Appropriative Rights and the Rule of Priority

Under the common law version of this doctrine, an appropriator acquired a water right by diverting unappropriated water from a natural stream and putting it to beneficial use.82 What “unappropriated” means in this context must be addressed in conjunction with one of the main features of this doctrine—which also explains its name—that is, time priority. Prior appropriation is governed by the principle “first in time, first in right,” meaning that those who first start diverting water in compliance with all applicable requirements (senior users) will have priority over water users who start diverting water at a later time (junior users).83

This mechanism becomes particularly relevant when flows are insufficient to supply water to all appropriators and those administering the system need to know which users are entitled to divert water and in what order. The answer under this doctrine is that the user with the earliest priority date will be able to satisfy the full amount covered by their right.84 After that, the appropriator with the second earliest priority date is next in line, and the process continues, allowing more junior users to divert any available water.85 It is worth highlighting that an appropriator with an early priority date may be located downstream from someone who is their junior.86 In these instances, the junior user will be able to divert water as long as enough is left in the stream—taking into account return flows—for the rights of downstream seniors to be fulfilled.87

Thus, when the focus is placed on the moment when the right is initially acquired, “unappropriated water” is often described as flows that are both physically and legally available. This requires water to be physically present so that it may actually be diverted, and also for it to not be committed to other users that have an existing right that will not be fulfilled unless that water remains in the stream.88

2. Scope, Transferability, and Loss of the Right

Determining the actual scope of a particular appropriative right can be challenging for a number of reasons. First, the measure of the right under the common law is determined by the amount of water that has been consistently put to beneficial use.89 This does not mean, however, that an appropriator must beneficially use 100% of the water that is diverted. Courts have explained that, though the water use must be efficient, some loss—typically conveyance loss—is permissible and considered part of the right.90 Conversely, water that is initially diverted but that is not used beneficially—for example, due to excessive conveyance loss or inefficient application—is considered “waste” and therefore not included in the appropriative right.91

The second consideration to be made with respect to the scope of the water right is that, in some jurisdictions, appropriative rights are constrained by the public trust doctrine. This doctrine, which can be traced back to Roman law, was later interpreted as treating lands under navigable waters to be “by the people of the State in their character as sovereign in trust for public uses.”92 While, initially, this principle only protected a limited number of public uses on the overlying waters—e.g., navigation, commerce, or fishing93—some states have decided to expand this list to include other uses, such as recreation and environmental protection.94 More importantly, the subsequent expansion of the doctrine has had important implications for the scope of appropriative rights. In the landmark decision National Audubon Society v. Superior Court, the California Supreme Court explained that appropriative rights subject to the public trust are limited by it, so that the rights cannot be exercised in ways that are harmful to the trust.95 It is important to point out that this expansion of the public trust doctrine has not taken place in all prior appropriation states. In fact, the legislature in Idaho has specifically provided that this doctrine does not apply to appropriative rights.96

Another key feature of appropriative rights is their transferability. The ability of appropriators to transfer their water rights has long been recognized by courts, and certain modifications to the right, such as changes in where the water is used, are now authorized by statute in all prior appropriation jurisdictions.97 Today, however, transfers typically require prior approval by state administrative agencies.98 While the requirements that the applicant must meet in order for the transfer to be cleared by the agency vary, one of the main challenges for the applicant is to prove that no junior appropriators will be injured by the reallocation of the right.99 A common scenario in which such injury can occur is if an appropriator who was diverting water from a point below a junior user transfers the water right to a third party who will now be taking that same amount of water but from a point above the junior user, thereby reducing the available flow in the stream in a manner that affects that junior user.100

The last feature of prior appropriation that should be highlighted is the possibility of losing a right in instances of nonuse. Under the common law doctrine of abandonment, water users can lose their right if the person bringing the claim of abandonment—typically, a junior user who would like to appropriate that water—can show that the water user is not exercising their right and intends to relinquish it.101 Some courts, however, have lightened the claimant’s burden by adopting a system where proof of a certain number of years of nonuse—the precise number varying across jurisdictions—raises a presumption of abandonment.102 Most states have also passed forfeiture statutes providing that appropriators will lose their right if they fail to exercise it within a certain number of years.103 While it may seem as though the application of this standard should be straightforward and simple, states have provided a number of exceptions to forfeiture or extensions to the maximum period of nonuse, for example, in situations in which the failure to put the water to use is the result of factors beyond the control of the appropriator.104 It is also worth noting that some states allow for water rights to be lost by prescription, that is, the close relative of the doctrine of adverse possession.105

III.  Are Water Rights Takings Property?

This part of the Article aims to determine the extent to which water rights should be considered takings property. This question, particularly in the context of appropriative rights, has generated ample controversy. Two water law scholars have noted that the law in this regard is “surprisingly unsettled.”106 Another scholar has explained—in part due to the uncertain status of water rights as takings property—that “the muddle that currently exists in takings jurisprudence is further exacerbated when applied to water right takings claims.”107 Yet another commentator has remarked that this question is one “with no consistent answers.”108

As noted earlier, however, there are two main possible approaches to determining whether a particular state-created right qualifies as takings property.109 First, a federal court may attempt to find an answer to this question in decisions originating in the relevant state court system.110 Second, a federal court may initially look to state law to identify the main features of the right and then make a separate assessment of whether the right in question meets the necessary requirements to be considered takings property.111

The following discussion will explore both of these avenues.112 Each of these two paths, however, require a very different methodological approach. The first focuses on whether appropriative rights are considered property at the state level, which is essentially an empirical question to be answered by examining the appropriate case law.113 The second operates under the assumption that there is a federal test—several have been proposed—for takings property and, therefore, the key inquiry is whether appropriative rights meet the requirements of the test in question.114

A. Are Appropriative Rights Property Under State Law?

As explained above, the question of whether states are consistently treating appropriative rights as property under state law is primarily an empirical one that is best answered by surveying state court opinions. This analysis will include case law of the states where the allocation of surface water is governed solely by prior Thus, states that have been characterized as following a hybrid model—including features of both riparianism or prior appropriation—will be excluded in order to minimize confusion.115 The resulting list of states is as follows: Alaska, Arizona, Colorado, Idaho, Montana, Nevada, New Mexico, Utah, and Wyoming.

The survey and analysis of the relevant case law confirms that the overwhelming majority of states that traditionally used prior appropriation as their surface water allocation method consider water rights to be property. Courts in most of these states—for example, Alaska, Colorado, Montana, New Mexico, and Wyoming—have specifically stated that a water right is or provides its holder with a “property right.”116 Other state courts, however, describe water rights as “vested rights,” implying that they should be viewed as property.117 Another subset of states—which partially overlap with the first category noted above—highlight both that water rights are vested and that they are property.118

The Nevada Supreme Court has reached the same conclusion by pointing out that, while water rights acquired both under the common law and by statute are appurtenant to land, they constitute a separate stick in the bundle.119 Courts in Idaho and Nevada have adopted an even clearer formulation of the notion that appropriative rights are property by stating that these water rights receive constitutional protections against uncompensated takings.120

Lastly, it is worth noting how courts in these states have characterized the nature of the property right that appropriators hold. Courts in a majority of these states have explicitly clarified that the property right that appropriators hold does not amount to ownership, but rather to a right to use water from a particular stream or other body of water.121

B. Do Appropriative Rights Meet the Definitions of Takings Property Advanced by Scholars and Courts?

Although most states have considered appropriative rights to be property, it is critical to subject these rights to further examination. As indicated earlier, some scholars would argue that these rights must satisfy certain tests before they can be deemed takings property under the United States Constitution.122

This raises the question: what is the appropriate test to apply in these cases? Given that several scholars have proposed different tests, the analysis will be organized based on the most basic formulation of the test, which is also the version that can be most easily traced back to Supreme Court precedent. This discussion, however, will also draw on the literature offering additional factors that should be considered when determining whether a right qualifies as property under the Takings Clause.

Professor John Echeverria’s observations on this question provide a very useful starting point for this analysis.123 This scholar explains that the Supreme Court has suggested that the Takings Clause should be interpreted as imposing certain limitations on the types of state interests that may be treated as property in this context.124 The main two requirements that an interest must meet to receive this protection are: (1) it “must include the authority to exclude others from accessing or using” it, and (2) it must be “specific and identifiable.”125 The following discussion will first examine whether appropriative rights would satisfy these two factors and will then explore additional prongs that the takings property test should incorporate.

1. The Right to Exclude

The phrase “right to exclude” is largely self-explanatory. However, it is worth noting that it captures the idea that those who have that right will be able to control access to—or “exclude others and prevent others from doing acts” with respect to—a thing, resource, etc.126 There is no question that the Supreme Court views the right to exclude as a key feature of property. In Kaiser Aetna v. United States, the court concluded that “the right to exclude” is “one of the most essential sticks in the bundle of rights that are commonly characterized as property.”127 The Court has quoted this language on numerous occasions from the 1980s to the present day, as evidenced in Cedar Point Nursery v. Hassid, a case decided in 2021.128

While no opinion of the Court has explicitly stated that the right to exclude is an essential factor to consider for takings purposes, it is reasonable to make this inference in light of the importance that this right has been given in cases involving constitutional property.129 Another way of justifying the notion that the right to exclude is a key component of takings property is that the Supreme Court has portrayed this right as “[t]he hallmark of a protected property interest” for the purposes of the Fifth Amendment when considering what qualifies as property under the Due Process Clause.130

As the analysis of state case law in Section III.A of this Article shows, state courts generally view the right to exclude as an inherent feature of appropriative rights. This should not be surprising given the critical role that priority of use plays in the administration of water systems governed by prior appropriation.131

Unlike with common law riparianism, which had the goal of allowing multiple water users share the resource equitably,132 one of the main principles of prior appropriation is that water users with an earlier priority date—i.e., senior users—will be able to divert all the available water recognized in the water right even if that means that there will be no water left for junior users.133 This is the essence of the right to exclude; senior appropriators can take the water to which they are entitled and exclude others by preventing them from using it.134 It is worth highlighting that this reasoning, while generally true for appropriative rights, does not necessarily hold for other types of water rights, such as riparian rights or certain types of groundwater rights.135

Professor Stern claims that, for a property right to be protected by the Takings Clause,136 it must be “good against the world.”137 This means that the right holder has the authority to decide how a thing or resource will be used.138 Logically, this includes the very right this Section is examining—that is, the right to exclude—as those who can determine how a thing or resource will be used can also decide who will not have access to it.139 Returning to the water context, holders of appropriative rights are able to determine how the water to which they are entitled under the priority system will be used, and they have the ability to exclude others from that water.140

It is important to note that this does not mean that, unless the authority to decide how a thing or resource will be used is unfettered, we should regard an appropriator as not having a right to exclude others.141 The right to use or control many other types of assets or resources—such as land—is not unlimited, and these limitations have not led courts to conclude that these other rights or interests do not qualify as property. For example, it is unquestionable that the owners of a piece of land in an urban residential area have the right to control it, even though they will very likely be subject to a number of restrictions, such as strict limitations with respect to the type of building they are able to erect. It is also highly unlikely that these landowners will be able to use the land to keep dangerous wild animals, to generate nuclear energy, or to store substantial amounts of hazardous substances.

2. Specific and Identifiable

While there is ample Supreme Court case law emphasizing that the right to exclude is a critical component of property rights, the Court’s support for the notion that a right must be “specific and identifiable” in order to qualify as a property right under the Takings Clause is weaker. Scholars who make this claim do not rely on a majority opinion of the Court, but rather on Justice Breyer’s dissent in Eastern Enterprises v. Apfel, in which three other Justices joined, as well as on Justice Kennedy’s concurrence in that same case.142          This view, however, has gained momentum more recently due to the Court’s analysis in Koontz v. St. John’s River Water Management District.143

The so-called “Breyer/Kennedy position”144 on this question was actually formulated in very general terms and set a rather low standard for what constitutes constitutional property. Justice Kennedy started by noting that “all of the cases where the regulatory taking analysis has been employed, a specific property right or interest has been at stake.”145 According to Justice Kennedy, there are numerous types of interests that meet this requirement,146 including “estate[s] in land,” “valuable interest[s] in an intangible (e.g., intellectual property),” and even “the right to extract mineral deposits.”147 Justice Breyer’s formulation of this requirement is also based on the general idea that “[t]he ‘private property’ upon which the [Takings] Clause traditionally has focused is a specific interest in physical or intellectual property.”148 What, then, would fail to meet this definition? Both Justices agreed that a government action that merely imposes a financial burden on a person or corporation without tying it to a particular asset or resource does not trigger the protections afforded by the Takings Clause.149

Under this interpretation, appropriative rights would meet this standard with ease. As explained at length earlier, water rights give their holder the right to use water.150 Acts interfering with this right would necessarily be tied to a physical resource—i.e., the water itself—rather than merely imposing a general financial burden on the water right holder.151 Therefore, water rights would satisfy the “specific and identifiable” requirement for constitutionally protected property under the broad and lenient view that Justices Breyer and Kennedy adopted.

Professor Thomas Merrill, however, offers a considerably narrower interpretation of this factor. While this alternative approach is not directly supported by Supreme Court precedent, it has the advantage of providing a clearer and richer framework to determine whether the “specific and identifiable” requirement is met. According to Merrill, this requirement is met if the interest in question is a “discrete asset” and not a mere “incident of property.”152 In other words, only when a discrete asset is present should an interest be viewed as “specific and identifiable.”153

The immediate question becomes: how does one know if a right is tied to a discrete asset? Merrill has explained that a discrete asset is (1) “a valued resource” that (2) “is held by the claimant in a legally recognized property form (for example, a fee simple, a lease, an easement, and so forth),” and (3) “is created, exchanged or enforced by economic actors with enough frequency.”154 This scholar provides the right to inherit as a useful example of a right that fails this test. Although the Supreme Court reached a different conclusion when it examined this type of interest in Hodel v. Irving,155 Merrill argues that the right to inherit does not meet the third prong of his test because it “is not a legally recognized form of property, nor is it created, exchanged, or enforced as a separate asset,” making it an incident of property rather than a discrete asset.156

Even if this stricter test is applied to appropriative water rights, the conclusion that the “specific and identifiable” requirement is met remains unchanged. First, water has been a valuable resource for a long time and its value has continued to increase in recent years.157 Second, as the examination of state court case law in Section III.A reveals, most states consider water rights to be a recognized form of property. Some may argue that they are a limited form of property,158 and while this is true, the consensus from a state common law standpoint is that appropriative rights are property.159

The third prong of the test includes three different options. A particular right may be either created, exchanged, or enforced frequently. While one of these elements would be sufficient to conclude that this condition is satisfied, water rights meet, at the very least, two of these requirements. Water rights are exchanged and enforced regularly. As noted earlier, most states allow sales and leases of appropriative rights, and these types of transfers occur regularly, even if these transactions may be subject to certain conditions to ensure the rational utilization of water resources and to prevent harm to existing appropriators.160

The preceding shows that appropriative rights meet the “specific and identifiable” requirement, including how Justices Breyer and Kennedy articulated it and Professor Merrill’s more refined version of that factor. This analysis would be incomplete, however, without addressing the extent to which water rights under prior appropriation also constitute what Professor James Stern refers to as a “discrete thing.”161 According to this scholar, this is one of the two distinguishing characteristics of in rem rights, which is relevant because Stern claims that in rem rights are property rights entitled to protection under both the Takings and Due Process Clauses.162

The “discrete thing” requirement is met when the right that is being analyzed gives authority over “a particular, identifiable item, resource, or asset.”163 This author provides a useful set of examples to clarify when this factor is or is not fulfilled. A right over a particular building is valuable and includes the ability to control it, whereas the right over an unspecified building lacks that quality and, consequently, does not confer a property right.164

As addressed in Part IV, applying these principles, which are primarily land- and chattel-centered, to other types of rights, such as those over water, creates numerous practical problems.165 The water to which an appropriator is entitled is not fully identified until it is diverted.166 This future access to water that the right protects, however, while uncertain, is nevertheless identifiable—the amount is fixed and so is the preference with which different appropriators will be able to divert the water, as well as their physical location in a water course or lake.167

Does this suffice to conclude that a water right meets Stern’s definition of a “discrete asset”? Unfortunately, this formulation of the “specific and identifiable” requirement does not provide a workable framework to answer this question.168 Part IV of this Article examines in detail why this occurs.169

The Supreme Court, however, has addressed a closely related question, that is, the extent to which a right to receive benefits in the future should be considered constitutional property for the purposes of the Due Process Clause.170 In Board of Regents of State Colleges v. Roth, the Court explained that:

The Fourteenth Amendment’s procedural protection of property is a safeguard of the security of interests that a person has already acquired in specific benefits. . . .

Thus, the Court has held that a person receiving welfare benefits under statutory and administrative standards defining eligibility for them has an interest in continued receipt of those benefits that is safeguarded . . . .171

Applying this reasoning analogically to the Takings Clause—which would be consistent with Stern’s view that the same definition of property should be used in both contexts—it is reasonable to conclude that an appropriative water right constitutes takings property. Stated differently, under this interpretation, the fact that appropriators do not presently have the ability to physically control the water that they are entitled to divert in the future does not prevent their right from being “concerned with some particular, singular, discrete thing.”

3. An Important Additional Factor: A Property Right Should Be Reasonably Irrevocable

Most of the formulations of the takings property test can be reduced to the two factors discussed above, that is, whether the right that is being examined (1) includes the right to exclude and (2) is “specific and identifiable.”172 According to Professor Merrill, even if a right meets the preceding requirements, an additional factor must be examined, that is, the interest must also be irrevocable to qualify as takings property.173

The “irrevocability” requirement sets a rather low bar that can be cleared by many types of rights. Professor Merrill posits that this factor is met when the right has a “certain degree of security expectation.”174 This author then clarifies that this simply means that “the right is not subject to discretionary revocation for some predetermined period of time.”175 It is critical to note the importance of the word “discretionary” in this context.176 Many rights can be revoked for a variety of reasons but far fewer can be taken away discretionarily. A term of years may be subject to certain conditions but is considered irrevocable under this factor.177 A common law license, on the other hand, can typically be revoked at any time and for any reason, and would therefore not satisfy this factor.178

Common law appropriative rights meet this standard, as they are typically not subject to discretionary revocation.179 Moreover, as discussed above, most courts consider appropriative rights to be vested once the water has been put to use.180 Some scholars have claimed that this factor is compromised, among other things, because this type of water right is subject to certain conditions that can lead to its reduction or even termination—e.g., by operation of the doctrines of forfeiture or abandonment.181 These two doctrines, however, will only lead to the cancelation of the right if certain conditions are met. In the case of forfeiture, the period of nonuse needs to extend beyond a certain number of years—e.g., three years in many jurisdictions.182 Even when that is the case, states frequently excuse the failure to use the water under a variety of circumstances.183 As for abandonment, courts typically require objective evidence supporting the conclusion that appropriators intended to permanently cease their diversion and beneficial use of water.184 Therefore, the termination of these rights under these two doctrines will have to be based on whether the aforementioned legal requirements are met, not on an agency’s or court’s discretionary judgment.

It is also worth noting that structural limitations of the right, such as restrictions stemming from the beneficial use requirement or the public trust doctrine, do not lead to the conclusion that the right is revocable. The fact that they may appear to constrain the exercise of an existing water right should be viewed, not as a curtailment of that right, but as an enforcement of limitations that, as the Supreme Court described in Lucas v. South Carolina Coastal Council, “inhere in the [right] itself.”185

If certain appropriators are wasting water by allowing excessive conveyance losses and an agency responds by ordering them to decrease their diversion, the effect of that mandate is not to partially revoke their right, but rather to prevent water users from removing more water than is covered by their right from a stream, river, or lake.186 Likewise, a court decision concluding that the public trust doctrine requires specific appropriators to reduce their water consumption is not modifying their existing rights but instead clarifying that, at that particular point in time, their water use is excessive.187 Therefore, by delineating the scope of the right, the enforcement of these restrictions helps answer the question: “how much water may an appropriator use?” This Article, however, is concerned with the threshold question of “does the appropriator have a property right in the use of water (regardless of its scope) to begin with?”

To be sure, in extreme cases, these two questions merge into one. For example, if when applying the public trust doctrine, an agency or court concludes that an appropriator may no longer divert any amount of water at any time, this would indeed amount to a revocation of the right. However, the mere existence of this possibility—in the small number of states that recognize the public trust doctrine as a limitation on water withdrawals188—does not invalidate the conclusion that appropriative rights have a “certain degree of security expectation” and should therefore be considered irrevocable for takings property purposes.

4. Conclusion: Are Appropriative Rights Takings Property?

Based on the above analysis, it is reasonable to conclude that common law appropriative rights meet all the necessary requirements to be considered constitutional property for takings purposes.189 To be sure, this does not mean that appropriative rights confer on their holder unlimited rights to the resource. On the contrary, and as explained in depth in Part II of this Article, their scope is limited in a variety of ways. For example, appropriators may only divert water that will be used for a useful or beneficial purpose.190

The conclusion that appropriative rights are takings property, despite having been challenged in the literature,191 is in line with the reasoning in multiple federal court opinions or, at the very least, consistent with their outcomes. In Casitas Municipal Water District v. United States, the Court of Federal Claims concluded that a water user’s right acquired under California law to divert water and put it to beneficial use was protected property for takings purposes.192 In a decision that has been criticized by a number of scholars,193 Tulare Lake Basin Water Storage District v. United States, the Court of Federal Claims noted that “the federal government, by preventing plaintiffs from using the water to which they would otherwise have been entitled . . . effected a . . . taking.”194 Given that a finding that a particular right is protected property is necessary in order to be able to conclude that a taking has occurred (i.e., a taking of that protected right), the court’s ultimate conclusion implies that the water right implicated in Tulare was takings property.

Viewing water rights as constitutionally protected property is also consistent with a series of Supreme Court cases decided in the early- to mid-nineteenth century. This is not to say that these decisions settled the issue. All these cases involved one particular type of water right—i.e., riparian rights.195 On the other hand, it is also important to note that the Court did not seem to rely on any feature that is distinctive to riparian rights when deciding these cases. In other words, there does not appear to be a good reason to suggest that the Court’s reasoning in these decisions would not equally apply to appropriative rights.

In International Paper Company v. United States, the Supreme Court found that the deprivation of water rights by the government constituted a taking.196 In that case, a power company had leased part of its water rights to International Paper and, as a result, the latter company’s ability to use water came to an end when the federal government required the power company to use all the water that could be diverted through its intake canal to generate power during World War I.197 The Court ultimately found that International Paper was entitled to compensation for the taking of its right to part of that water.198 This implies that the Court viewed a right to use water—which, in this case, had its origin in a contract—as protected under the Takings Clause.

In United States v. Gerlach Live Stock Company, the construction of a dam that was part of the California Central Valley Project interfered with downstream landowners’ right to have their grasslands watered through the seasonal overflow from the water body adjoining their land.199 The Court noted that the federal government had consistently recognized that water rights acquired under state law were in fact property rights and proceeded to uphold the lower court’s decision to award compensation to the landowner plaintiffs.200 It is also noteworthy that the majority, by recognizing the landowners’ right to compensation, rejected the argument advanced by Justice Douglas that “there are no private property rights in the waters of a navigable river.”201

Two subsequent opinions also relating to the impacts of the Central Valley Project on the use of water by riparian landowners further clarified that the water rights involved in these litigations constituted takings property. In Ivanhoe Irrigation District v. McCracken, the Court made it clear that the federal government’s acquisition of water rights from private parties required the payment of compensation, whether through the exercise of eminent domain or in the context of a takings claim brought by the water right holders.202 Five years later, in Dugan v. Rank, the Court explained that the government’s interference with the plaintiffs’ water rights deprived the owners of their use of the water and created a servitude that had the effect of taking their property for which compensation was due.203

These Supreme Court opinions have been used to support the claim that interferences with water rights constitute physical takings requiring the payment of compensation.204 It is important to highlight, however, that this is not the claim that is being made here. On the contrary, these decisions serve to illustrate the fact that viewing water rights as takings property is consistent with Supreme Court precedent. This Article does not express an opinion as to whether a physical or regulatory takings framework should be used to analyze if a reduction or destruction of such right requires the payment of compensation, a question which others have explored at length.205

A final point to consider is that the conclusion that water rights are takings property is also consistent with how these types of rights are viewed in other jurisdictions. For example, Article 19.24 of the Chilean Constitution provides that citizens may not be deprived of their property without the payment of Interestingly, this same constitutional provision contains a specific reference to water rights and notes that water rights are “property.”206 Another civil law jurisdiction provides an additional example of how rights to use water can be viewed as takings property. The Constitutional Court of Spain concluded that constitutional protections against takings extend to any economic right, including a right to use property or resources that belong to the public, such as water.207

C. A Brief Note on Riparian Rights as Takings Property

Although this Article aims to assess the soundness and usefulness of takings property definitions by applying them to appropriative water rights, it seems appropriate to briefly address some of the issues that arise when testing these same frameworks against the other main type of surface water rights in the United States, that is, riparian rights.208 While under the common law, the owners of riparian lands held a wide variety of rights—including the right to use water, to access water, to build wharves, etc.209—the following analysis will focus, to maintain consistency throughout Part III of this Article, on the right to use water.

Two factors of the takings property framework provided by Professor Merrill could be viewed as compromised in the case of riparian rights, namely, the right to exclude and the “specific and identifiable” requirement.210 With regard to the first, one could argue that riparians’ right to exclude is significantly weaker than that enjoyed by appropriators. This is due to the fact that, unlike with prior appropriation, where seniority comes with the right to exclude junior users from the resource in times of scarcity, riparians do not have that same prerogative.211

However, the differences between the two systems with respect to the right to exclude should not be overstated. Even under the common law, riparian owners were entitled to prevent the vast majority of the population from using water from the river or lake abutting their property—they were able to exclude everyone except other riparians.212 Moreover, under modern versions of this doctrine—i.e., regulated riparianism—the administering agency will often abstain from granting new permits when all the water in the system has been allocated to existing users.213 This effectively allows a permit holder to exclude potential new water users with the assistance of an agency or court.

The second issue is that one could question that a riparian’s right to use water is ” by arguing that this right is not property but merely an incident of property attached to the ownership of land.214 The basis for this argument would be that, especially under the early common law, water could only be used on riparian land.215 The fact that the right could not be separated from the land to which it was attached—e.g., by transferring it to a nonriparian user—would lend some support to the claim that a riparian’s prerogative to use water was just a stick in the landowner’s bundle.216

Some state courts, however, explicitly rejected this reasoning and treated a riparian landowner’s right to use water as a separate property right.217 Moreover, it is also worth noting that even if a riparian right is considered an incident of property, a takings claim brought by a landowner whose water rights have been abrogated is not necessarily destined to fail. Even in these instances, riparians may be able to prevail—the likelihood of that success would depend to a significant extent on the takings test employed—by arguing that the governmental interference with their water rights substantially diminishes the value of their land.218

IV. Broader Lessons on Takings Property

The analysis in Part III achieved two main goals. The first was to answer the question of whether appropriative rights, despite being treated by courts as common law property, should be viewed as takings property as well. The second was to test existing takings property definitions against a right—again, an appropriative water right—that presents a variety of unusual characteristics that set them apart from more traditional interests in land or personal property.219

This Part of the Article provides and contextualizes a number of insights that can be extracted from the analysis in Part III and that are particularly relevant to the constitutional property literature. These broader lessons have a common theme, namely, that scholars have looked at the notion of constitutional property from an unnecessarily narrow lens: one that focuses on land, chattel, and other very specific rights that the Supreme Court has examined in the past. The following discussion addresses some of the flaws in takings property frameworks.

A. Existing Scholarship Shows an Excessive Reluctance to Consider “Non-Land” as Takings Property

One of the main arguments that scholars have made to support the claim that water rights should not be viewed as takings property is that they are “too unlike land.”220 This view reflects the idea that one should be hesitant to view rights that do not relate to land—or, possibly, certain objects—as property. The question this raises is: is it justified to exclude other types of rights from this category of property ab initio?

1. The Claim that Usufructuary Rights Cannot Be Considered Takings Property

Court opinions and scholarship on water rights contain a number of arguments that are frequently deployed to question the status of water as a property right. Chief among them is the notion that can be summarized with the phrase “[n]o one has any property in the water itself but a simple usufruct.”221 Stated differently, the argument is that rights that are usufructuary in nature cannot be deemed takings property.222

It is critical to distinguish this claim from the position that other courts have adopted on this question, that is, that a usufruct, while a property right, does not constitute full ownership.223 While these two views may seem similar at first blush, they are markedly different. In one case, the argument is that a right to use is not a constitutionally protected property right while, in the other, courts are merely providing a reminder that, as explained in more detail below, a right to use is one of the property rights in the bundle, rather than the full bundle.224

Focusing on the former position, the main problem with it is its untenable premise that a usufructuary right cannot be a property right. A usufruct, a familiar type of right in civil law jurisdictions,is “[a] right for a certain period to use and enjoy the fruits of another’s property without damaging or diminishing it.”225 This so-called “real right” confers direct control over a thing owned by another person226 or, in other words, a possessory right of use.227 Thus, a usufruct and a life estate are functional equivalents, particularly in cases in which the usufruct’s duration is measured by the life of the person holding the right.228

For this reason, putting the label “usufructuary” on a particular right should have the effect of reinforcing, rather than diminishing, its consideration as a property right. In the land context, for example, it would be shocking to argue that a life estate is not takings property. Since the 1960s, this has been treated as a truism in the literature, which focused on a subsequent step of the takings analysis, namely, how compensation should be split between the life tenant and the holder of the future interest, often a remainder.229 Even easements—the nonpossessory version of the right to use and, therefore, a more limited right—are overwhelmingly viewed as takings property.230

Consequently, the argument that, in the nonland context, a more robust version of a right to use should not be regarded as takings property is hard to justify, unless the reason for this inconsistent treatment is simply that land is different and therefore subject to a different set of rules when it comes to determining which rights in it will be deemed property.

2. Applying the Transferability Requirement for Takings Property to Water Rights

As explained earlier, Professor Merrill’s test for takings property is narrower than that adopted by courts and other scholars.231 One of the elements relevant to his proposed framework is whether a particular right is transferable, which is part of the inquiry on whether an asset is “discrete.”232

Under Merrill’s test, a discrete asset is present when “a valued resource . . . held by the claimant in a legally recognized property form (for example, a fee simple, a lease, an easement, and so forth), . . . is created, exchanged or enforced by economic actors with enough frequency.”233 Therefore, whether a valued resource can be exchanged—i.e., is transferable—may play an important role in deciding if the discrete asset requirement is met. It is worth noting, however, that based on the wording of the test, a right would not necessarily need to be transferable to meet this requirement, as rights created or enforced with enough frequency would qualify as well.

While, even under Merrill’s framework, a nontransferable right could be deemed takings property, some water law scholars have argued that water rights do not satisfy the “discrete asset” requirement because they cannot “be routinely conveyed or disposed of however the appropriator wishes.”234 This approach, however, constitutes a significant departure from Merrill’s test. As noted above, transferability is not a necessary prerequisite of the “discrete asset” requirement. More importantly, Merrill refers to transferability “by economic actors with enough frequency,” not an unlimited ability to transfer and dispose of the right.

The effect of adopting this new and considerably stricter standard specifically for water rights is that it creates an inconsistency with how more traditional property rights are analyzed. As explained earlier, the limitations on the transferability of water rights are far from absolute.235 While most prior appropriation jurisdictions require administrative approval of transfers, most of these requests will be approved as long as the modification of the right does not injure other appropriators.236

If this type of restriction on alienability were sufficient to conclude that appropriative rights are not transferable and, therefore, not takings property, this same standard would lead to the very questionable conclusion that a fee simple absolute is not takings property either. It is not uncommon to see instances in which land transfers are subject to conditions or administrative approval. For example, a New Jersey statute requires owners of industrial sites to either submit a cleanup plan or a declaration certifying that there are no hazardous substances on the property as a condition precedent to their transfer.237 More generally, restraints on alienation are frequently upheld by courts as long as they are deemed reasonable.238

Sections IV.A.1 and IV.A.2 show that arguments that scholars have made to claim that water rights should not be considered takings property would not be persuasive in the land context. This ultimately reveals that these arguments are predicated on the idea that land is different and, therefore, property interests that do not pertain to land should enjoy a lower status in our legal system.

B. The “Specific and Identifiable” Requirement for Takings Property and the in Rem/in Personam Rights Distinction

All the takings property tests discussed in this Article incorporate the requirement that a right be “specific and identifiable”—or a “discrete thing” or “discrete asset”—in order to qualify as takings property.239 To apply these tests in specific cases, however, one has to deal with an extremely complex question, that is, how should the determination of whether a right is sufficiently “specific and identifiable” be made? Even more important, however, is the question of which of these different answers provides better outcomes, an issue on which the analysis of appropriative rights can shed some light.

1. Two Possible Answers: “Discrete Asset” and “Identified with Enough Specificity”

As explained earlier, scholars have proposed different approaches to answer this question.240 As addressed at length in Part III, Professor Merrill has concluded that this requirement—to which he refers as a “discrete asset”—is met when the right relates to (1) “a valued resource” that (2) “is held by the claimant in a legally recognized property form (for example, a fee simple, a lease, an easement, and so forth),” and (3) “is created, exchanged or enforced by economic actors with enough frequency.”241

An alternative to this framework is one that, relying on the distinction between in personam and in rem rights, essentially argues for a different interpretation of the “specific and identifiable” requirement.242 Professor Stern, the main proponent of this in rem theory of constitutional property, posits that the notion of takings property—as well as other types of constitutional property—overlaps with that of in rem rights.243 Because, according to this scholar, one of the key features of in rem rights is that the thing must be “identified with enough specificity,” this effectively provides a way to interpret the “specific and identifiable” requirement that is different from Merrill’s.244

Of course, the next logical step is to define the precise meaning of the phrase “identified with enough specificity.” The basic idea is that the interest in question must be described in such a way that does more than merely identify quantities or substitutes of the thing.245

This approach leads to coherent outcomes when one applies it to rights over land or personal property. For instance, it is reasonable to view the obligation of a widget manufacturer to provide a certain number of widgets of a particular quality to a customer as an in personam—or contract—right.246 The things are described in terms of quantities and, therefore, they would not be considered “identified with enough specificity.” The same is true when a developer agrees to build a house that will meet certain specifications. Under this view, property rights would basically attach only when the thing comes into existence and is delivered, that is, when the widgets are made and identified as the customer’s or when the house is built and title passes to the buyer.

2. Why the “Identified with Enough Specificity” Approach Leads to Suboptimal Outcomes

As noted above, applying Merrill’s test to appropriative rights shows that this approach leads to predictable and consistent conclusions.247 Relying on the in rem/in personam distinction to argue that things must be “identified with enough specificity” to qualify as takings property, however, yields intuitively sound outcomes when applied to land and personal property but raises some concerning issues in the water context. Section II.A explains that water rights have two different components.248 The first allows the holder to use the water once it has been diverted and the second protects the right to divert and use water in the future.249

If we apply the “in rem theory of constitutional property” to appropriative rights, which adds the constraint that a right may only be considered “specific and identifiable” once it can actually be identified, as well as the limitation that quantities are not sufficient, we would reach a surprising conclusion. The part of an appropriative right that focuses on the use of water that has already been diverted—what I have referred to earlier as “present water”250—would constitute takings property. At that point in time, it would be theoretically possible to identify the specific molecules that the appropriator is entitled to use. On the other hand, the second part of the right—i.e., the forward-looking component that I described as “future water”251—might not qualify as takings property as the water molecules that may be diverted and used in the future, while in existence, have not been, and cannot at this point be, identified.252

This conclusion, of course, is not objectionable per se. It does, however, raise an important issue. Given that “[a]ll rights are . . . either in rem or in personam,” if the right to divert and use water in the future is not an in rem right, we should expect it to instead be in personam or contractual.253 How plausible is it, however, that water rights could be viewed as in personam?

To determine whether water rights could potentially be considered in personam, a more detailed analysis of what this conclusion would entail is in order. First of all, it is important to note that, while in personam rights are typically contractual in nature, they are a broader category that includes, in addition to contracts, for example, rights that arise out of a judicial judgment.254 In personam rights are more generally defined as those requiring a specific person to behave in a certain way.255 For this reason, they bind particular individuals only.256 Wesley Hohfeld famously defined rights in personam as “unique right[s] residing in a person (or group of persons) and availing against a single person (or single group of persons).”257 Given that contracts are the epitome of in personam rights, it is not surprising that, consistently with this, one scholar highlighted that in personam rights tend to impose positive—rather than negative—duties.258

Given how in personam rights are characterized in the literature, it would be complicated to conclude that common law appropriative rights fit within this category. The holder of the right is not entitled to require a particular person to act a certain way. In other words, no one has the obligation to provide water to the appropriator—not nature, not the government, and not any other person.259 Moreover, the time priority feature of prior appropriation makes the argument that appropriative rights are in personam even less plausible. The obligation to not interfere with senior users is a negative one, a trait commonly associated with rights in rem as noted above.260 Further, this duty applies not to a single person or group thereof but to a “large and indefinite class of persons”—i.e., anyone who could be in a position to interfere with that right.261 This, again, is another distinctive feature of rights in rem.262

This analysis shows the contradiction that water rights uncover. Water itself cannot be identified before it is diverted, which suggests that these rights are not “identified with enough specificity” and therefore not in rem or takings property. However, the preceding analysis focusing on the features of each type of right shows that appropriative rights are more properly classified as in rem rather than in personam.

3. Addressing the Contradiction and a Path Forward: In Rem vs. In Re Rights

The “in rem theory of constitutional property” would be creating a new category of rights, thereby undermining the idea that rights must be either in personam or in rem. This third category of rights would have to include rights that, as appropriative rights, exhibit the features of a right in rem—and are therefore not in personam rights—but that are not “identified with enough specificity” and, therefore, would not be considered takings property under the “in rem theory of constitutional property.” This is problematic in that this situation is ultimately negating the main premise on which this particular approach to identifying takings property is based, namely that in rem rights are synonymous with constitutional property. The reason for this contradiction can ultimately be traced back to the premise that in rem rights must be “identified with enough specificity,” excluding a reference to quantities. This requirement is making the in rem rights category exceedingly narrow.

A way to address this analytical obstacle is to focus on Hohfeld’s distinction between two similar but different categories of rights—rights in re and rights in rem. According to this scholar, the notion of in re rights is narrower—and included within the broader category of in rem rights—and typically relates to tangible objects, such as land or personal property.263 Rights in rem, on the other hand, include but do not necessarily always concern a thing or tangible object.264 Therefore, interpreting the requirement that a thing be identified “with enough specificity” to mean that quantities or substitutes should be excluded would be to effectively use the category of in re rights, rather than that of in rem rights, as the standard for constitutional property.

This should clarify why a third category of rights is not in fact being created. Returning to the water example, as explained above, appropriative rights are rights in rem and, therefore, not in personam. Given their peculiar characteristics—i.e., they are not land or personal property—they cannot be included in the subcategory of in rem rights that Hohfeld and others refer to as in re.

Returning to the problem with how the “in rem theory of constitutional property” defines rights in rem, a solution would be to use the traditional definition of rights in rem to determine which rights qualify as takings property. In other words, by recognizing that rights in rem do not require the existence of a discrete, tangible thing that is described “with enough specificity,” the contradiction would be eliminated, and the focus would be on rights that have traditionally been considered in rem rather than in re. This is also consistent with the view, endorsed by the Supreme Court and discussed in more detail earlier, that a right to continue receiving something valuable in the future—as occurs with water rights—can be a property right entitled to constitutional protection under the Fifth Amendment.265

This does not mean, however, that the notion of a “discrete and identifiable” asset should be eliminated from takings property tests. What would change is how courts determine whether that requirement is met or not. Instead of relying on the idea that identifying quantities or substitutes of the thing is inconsistent with property rights for takings purposes, the focus would be placed exclusively on other considerations already present in other takings property frameworks—for example, the approach proposed by Professor Thomas Merrill.

As the water right example shows, basing such a definition on considerations such as frequent creation, enforceability, and transferability of the right is a far superior approach.266 In addition to avoiding the tensions that equating in re and takings property creates, Merrill’s interpretation leads to more consistency between how interests in land and other less traditional rights are treated for takings protection purposes.

Conclusion

Determining what “private property” means in the context of the Takings Clause is critical, especially when courts are dealing with rights or interests whose status as takings property has been questioned. This is particularly relevant, for example, when plaintiffs in a takings case are arguing that they should be compensated for the modification of a water right or claim that business losses associated with a shutdown order issued during a pandemic constitutes a taking.

Scholars who support the idea that there is a specific definition of property for takings or, more broadly, constitutional purposes, have been grappling with the challenges of providing a test to make these determinations. As this Article has explained, the tests that have been proposed in the literature are consistent and predictable when dealing with traditional rights, especially those in land. However, when tested against more idiosyncratic rights such as water rights, their differences and shortcomings become apparent.

This Article has shown that frameworks that interpret the Supreme Court’s “specific and identifiable” language by focusing on features of a right such as transferability and whether they are an accepted form of property under the common law lead to sounder outcomes than those adopting a very narrow view of the requirement that is only satisfied if the resource is identified with the utmost precision. It is also crucial for these tests to be applied consistently so that the bar for what is required for a particular right to be deemed takings property is not lower for some rights—for example, those in land—than it is for other less traditional rights, such as a water right in prior appropriation jurisdictions.


* Assistant Professor, Gonzaga University School of Law. For helpful conversations and comments, I would like to thank Daniel Cole, John Echeverria, Robert Fischman, Jessica Kiser, Agnieszka McPeak, Heather Payne, and the participants in the Rocky Mountain Junior Scholars Forum and the Online Workshop for Environmental Scholarship. For excellent research assistance, I would like to thank Maxim Poudrier-Tudan, Kiefer Stenseng, and Stephen Wright.