Staying in the Takings Lane: The Compensation Issue in Cedar Point Nursery

The Supreme Court held in Cedar Point Nursery v. Hassid that a California regulation mandating that union organizers have occasional access to privately owned farms was a per se taking because it stripped the farm owners of the right to exclude. The decision almost certainly departed from prior law, and I briefly review some of the critiques of the majority opinion. But my focus is on questions that arise if one accepts the Court’s conclusion that the regulation is indeed a taking: First, I briefly discuss whether we should permit the taking so long as the owners are compensated or enjoin the taking either because it is not “for public use” or because compensation, a form of damages, is not an adequate remedy for losses that are either not readily commensurable with money or are extraordinarily difficult to measure. Second, I discuss how we should measure compensable losses and, more particularly, whether we should compensate owners because the regulation makes them more vulnerable to what they see as profit-reducing unionization. I note that the fact that a plaintiff might not have sustained reputational losses absent a trespass that gave the trespassers access to reputation-damaging information does not mean that the damages for trespass should incorporate the damages for reputational losses (which should instead be assessed by reference to a different “track” of law, defamation law). What the owners in Cedar Point Nursery are entitled to is compensation only for the loss of rights that physical takings law protects—in cases like this of temporary access mandates, losses that inhere in having to share use of a portion of the property with others—and we must deal with the validity of laws limiting the capacity to suppress unionization efforts in their own right.

 

Introduction

In Cedar Point Nursery v. Hassid (hereafter CPN),1 the Supreme Court decided that California regulations passed pursuant to the California Agricultural Labor Relations Act of 1975, mandating that union organizers have access to privately owned farms, 120 days a year, during three non-work hours, constituted a per se taking. The Court held that the regulation took the regulated owners’ property because it stripped them of the right to exclude, thereby constituting the sort of physical taking that the Court first announced in Loretto v. Teleprompter Manhattan CATV Corp. would require compensation.2 The Court did so without regard to the explicit factors articulated in Penn Central Transport Co. v. New York City3 that courts use to ascertain if a regulation has gone “too far” in asking an owner to bear the costs of meeting a public end.4 Less doctrinally, but more substantively, the Court acted without regard to whether the regulation forced a particular owner to bear unreasonably high costs that should be more widely borne or interfered with aspects of control over how one’s resources are used that should be protected.5

The decision poses a multitude of questions, and I will make but modest reference to many of the problems in the decision that its critics have pointed out.6 I will also attend even more briefly to the question of whether the nursery owner should be entitled to enjoin the access-granting regulation or merely be awarded monetary compensation, a question the district court might well face on remand, although the owners in the case initially sought only declaratory and injunctive relief, not compensation.7

What I will focus on a bit more is a question the district court might well have to face on remand if the state presses the point that the Fifth Amendment protects owners against uncompensated takings for public use, not the takings themselves: how to measure just compensation in this case. The critical point I will pursue is that it would be inappropriate simply to ascertain and compensate for all the losses the owner bears as a result of the regulation. We should make sure that we do not use takings law to protect economic interests that we have rightly decided are not worthy of protection, either through takings law or outside of it. In reaching this conclusion, I draw on analogies from other areas of law. For instance, it is appropriate to protect only certain interests that a landowner has against what might be considered technical trespasses, even when the economic losses borne that could be said to be caused by these putative trespasses may be considerably more extensive than the properly compensable ones.8 Similarly, it is inappropriate to defeat a defendant’s claim that her use of copyrighted material was a fair use by noting that she caused a high level of economic harm to the copyright holder, rather than that she harmed a narrower set of economic interests appropriately protected through copyright law.9 I will briefly argue, further, that the properly compensable losses in this case are likely to be trivial,10 though perhaps not as trivial as the lower courts found them to be in the canonical Loretto case.11

I.  Some Standard Critiques of the CPN Decision

Most of the critiques of CPN focus either on whether the Court’s efforts to distinguish the case from PruneYard Shopping Ctr. v. Robins or Heart of Atlanta Motel v. United States are successful; whether the ways in which the cases might indeed be distinguishable are meaningful or merely expose the substantive hollowness of treating either exclusion/physical appropriation cases differently than use regulations; or whether the holding in the case dictates (or at least modestly foreshadows) problematic rulings that would require the government to pay compensation when it sends inspectors (e.g. health and safety or environmental enforcement inspectors) on to private property.

Property owners in both PruneYard and Heart of Atlanta Motel were certainly stripped of the legal privilege to exclude persons that they desired to exclude (political protesters; non-White potential customers respectively). How might one differentiate the cases from CPN?12 And why might the distinctions seem problematic, either because they cannot be administered in a sensible or predictable fashion or in the sense that the distinctions, even if discernible enough to predict outcomes, are substantively empty—differentiating situations along dimensions that ought to be of no moment?

One might argue that the owners in both PruneYard and Heart of Atlanta did not seek to exclude persons generally from entering their property and the governmental regulations at issue (merely?) sought to bar the owners from banning invitees on the basis of their identity or the uses that the invitees would make of the property. By contrast, in the majority’s view, CPN generally maintained a robust right to exclude, inviting in only people to perform a narrow set of functions.13

But of course, one can readily describe the CPN owners as inviting a wide range of strangers (e.g. workers, suppliers), such that they would not be said to have the sorts of privacy-protecting, anti-intrusion interests that, say, a homeowner would have, and argue that the CPN owners were acting to exclude solely on the basis of something akin either to the identity of the invitees (union organizers barred, not those delivering alternative political messages) or, even more plausibly, the use they intended to make (labor organizing, not supplying inputs for the nursery business). Or, conversely, one can say that the owners in PruneYard sought to issue a limited invitation rather than to open the shopping center to all comers: we want shoppers, browsers, and mall rats, but not those who have come to engage in political speech, particularly because political speakers may suppress shopping.

Determining when an entity is sufficiently open to the public to permit this sort of regulation without compensation will plainly pose serious administrative challenges even if one ignores the degree to which it is a substantively irrelevant basis to distinguish among fundamentally commercial enterprises. If CPN had a small retail store or wholesale showroom on the premises, would that have been enough to change the result? Are a nursery’s suppliers the sort of limited invitees who do not count as members of the public generally that the Court has in mind if they come only by appointment, and do they lose that status and become more like the members of the public who come to the mall if they come at unscheduled times?

The Court notes that an owner has no right to demand compensation when the state’s regulation “merely asserts a preexisting limitation upon an owner’s title.”14 The Court here is drawing on its decision in Lucas v. South Carolina Coastal Council,15 in which the Court noted that a regulation that wiped out the entire economic value of an owner’s parcel by requiring him to abate a nuisance would not constitute a taking, even though it had wiped out all economic value, because the owner never had the right to create a nuisance in the first instance.16 The Lucas background principles/nuisance exception that the CPN court carries forward has two plausible interpretations in my view. The first is, as dissenters in both Lucas and CPN noted, both extraordinarily difficult to apply and subject to the charge that utilizing it invokes the specter of unwarranted imposition of judicial policy predilections.17 The second interpretation is somewhat more defensible, but it is fairly plainly inapplicable to the owners in CPN.

The first interpretation I would proffer is that the supposed pre-existing limits on exclusion or use rights are the only apt limits to account for because they have the historical pedigree that entitles committed Burkeans to believe they are wise or because the Court has concluded that these well-pedigreed limits are the only ones consistent with pre-political natural rights. In this view, the owner is protected from value-destroying regulation unless the regulation merely imposes justified limits on his use rights, and the only justified limits are these long-recognized ones.

Any rule that respects pre-existing limits is difficult to apply both because the content of historically established limits is difficult to discern,18 and, more importantly, because it is not clear how long a limit on rights has to be established (or by whom?) before it qualifies as a pre-existing limit. Is Title II of the 1964 Civil Right Act (or the older-still state antidiscrimination laws that preceded it) old enough now that limits on discriminatory exclusion would count as pre-existing if there were a 2022 Heart of Atlanta challenge? Are the nearly fifty-year-old legislative limits set by the state of California to exclude farm union organizers pre-existing enough? And if the Court is fixated, consciously or not, on the distinction between legislative and judicially imposed limits, would we consider limits on the reach of trespass law imposed by the New Jersey court in the 1971 case of State v. Shack,19 pre-existing limits on the right to exclude? 20

And, of course, if the idea is that there is some set of identifiable pre-existing rights that get the balance between access and exclusion claims or use and immunity claims just right, we face obvious problems of judicial overreach and the illegitimate translation of the ideological preferences of some set of common law judges into immutable legal rules. Justice Blackmun made that point forcefully in his dissent in Lucas21 as does Justice Breyer in his CPN dissent.22

The nuisance exception in Lucas might, however, be defended not because judges in bygone nuisance cases had special insight into what uses should be protected and which banned as a substantive matter, but because only owners who expected to make uses that were already barred by pre-existing law were at fault for purchasing the property for more than it is worth in its regulated state. In that sense, the pre-existing law exception is meant to distinguish cases in which an owner reasonably relied on her property having a particular level of value that was wiped out by regulation she should not have been expected to anticipate and those in which the owner simply overpaid for the property and now seeks to be insured against her own bad decisions. This second argument is quite problematic on its own terms: it is hardly clear in the Lucas context that an owner who does not see restrictive environmental legislative regulation coming is any more reasonable in his purchasing decisions than one who does not see how a nuisance suit might be resolved if he engages in his favored activity. But even if one is persuaded by this version of the argument generally, it would not help the owners in CPN because they did not, and likely could not, allege that they (or their predecessors in interest) paid a substantial premium for the parcel relying on the ability to exclude labor organizers.

In attempting to defend the decision from what even the majority seem to see as an unwanted result—that it would demand that government compensate owners if government inspectors were granted the privilege to enter an owner’s property to check for health, safety, or environmental violations—the majority argue that these inspections would not require compensation because the right to inspect would be a valid “condition” that the government demands in exchange for the gratuitous privilege to engage in regulated activity.23 If one makes the majority’s argument broad enough—everyone who is allowed to operate a business has surrendered rights to be free from reasonable inspection in exchange for that privilege to operate—then the conditional benefit line of cases proves too much. The Court in Horne v. Department of Agriculture specifically rejects the idea that the “privilege” to engage in a generally legal business is the sort of special governmental permit or privilege that might justify an uncompensated exaction, a surrender of a property interest that would correct the “problems” caused by permitting the activity.24 And while it is true that some businesses that are subject to inspection require special licenses to operate, in the same way that the Nollans required a specifically granted building permit, inspectors frequently inspect land that is not operated under permit.25

By relying on the line of cases that differentiate breaches of the right to exclude (which may or may not be fully coterminous with cases in which the state appropriates property),26 the Court continued to distract attention from the relevant substantive question: should either the owner or the state, as a matter of course, find use regulation any more or less troubling than exclusion regulation?

Professor Michael McConnell argues that the state must be restrained more (by requiring compensation) when it chooses to appropriate rather than regulate because it will always be more tempted to grab property that it can (re)distribute to favored constituents rather than merely limit what an owner can do with her own property.27 He makes this argument in the context of defending the Horne decision that he had litigated.28 The government would be far less prone to stop farmers from producing or selling raisins (the deferentially reviewed regulatory method of supply-reducing cartelization, to put it in negative terms, or the preservation of industries with high average cost/very low marginal cost structures to put it more positively) than to seize raisins, which would be attractive not only if in the interests of the rent-seeking/industry-protecting farmers but attractive because the raisins could be distributed to other favored constituencies.29

Even if this were marginally true in Horne itself—and how incremental the change in the government’s motive to act would have been depends on the relative weight of its motive to support crop prices compared to the desire to distribute food to schoolchildren or foreign aid programs—it is hardly a general feature distinguishing use regulation from “appropriation.” This has seemed obvious both to those on the Right, like Richard Epstein, who favor more aggressive policing of regulation,30 and those who are far more skeptical that there is a coherent set of starting place entitlements that permit us to identify when constitutional property rights are breached. If the state is trying to satisfy demands by those seeking to reduce development density (whether to increase the value of their already-developed properties or out of other-regarding environmental sentiments) it does so just as well through use regulation as through condemnations to convert previously developable property to open space. If the state is trying to transfer housing resources, in-kind, to disadvantaged renters, it does so just as well through regulatory rent control as through using the condemnation power to acquire land for low-cost housing development. And, ironically perhaps, in CPN itself, if the state’s goal is to give a goodie to politically favored unions, it can do so far more readily by taking actions that force owners to allow union organizers to be able to interact with workers that are at worst at the border of use regulation, than to appropriate the nursery owner’s property outright. If the state had engaged in more unambiguous appropriative conduct, seizing some of the nursery’s property and declaring it the “Union Organizer Speaking Place,” the nursery could still, absent further regulation, have taken steps to ensure workers did not come anywhere near the government-owned physical parcel.31

II.  Injunction Versus Compensation: Of Public Use and the Inadequacy of Damages

Under the deferential “public use” tests articulated by the majority in Kelo v. City of New London,32 it is plain that the taking, if it is indeed a taking, in CPN would meet the public use requirement and therefore merely be compensable, rather than barred. The state’s action would be in furtherance of a plan to further a “public purpose” and that would be that.33 It seems equally clear to me that were today’s Court to decide a case like Kelo, it would adopt Justice Thomas’s dissenting opinion in the case, arguing that the state has not condemned property for public use (and therefore cannot proceed with the condemnation) unless post-condemnation, the property is “owned” by the state or an entity with common carrier obligations.34

Thomas’s test is ambiguous in many ways,35 and ill-conceived as a policy matter in still more ways,36 but in thinking about CPN, only one ambiguity matters: Did Thomas consider whether the public use requirement as he understood it applies not just to condemnations but to regulatory takings in which others are either granted use rights or merely benefit from the curtailment of another’s use, disposition, or exclusion rights (arguably the case in, for example, zoning, restrictive environmental regulation, rent control, disability accommodation requirements, perpetuities reforms that wipe out reversion interests that would have vested had the traditional rule remained in force or reforms limiting the life of defeasible fees)?

To the degree that he would forbid the taking unless there is something like public (or common carrier) ownership of the benefits of that taking, I am skeptical that the purported taking in CPN should be permitted under his test. Only a small subset of the public (union organizers) gains a right as a result of the regulation. Read this way, though—and I am not really sure how to read Justice Thomas on this issue—a wide swath of regulatory takings should be barred, not merely subject to compensation duties. Only tenants benefitted by rent control directly gain anything from the controls or could be said to own the landlord’s taken freedom of disposition; only those whose use of public accommodations is facilitated by accommodation requirements directly use the facilitative accommodations;37 and, even more obviously, only those whose property is unencumbered when old possibilities of reverter get wiped out directly own the taken property. Think also about right-to-farm laws that at least arguably take the immunity rights of potential plaintiffs in nuisance suits: the use rights that the farmers gain when potential plaintiffs are stripped of immunity rights are owned by the farmers, not by the public generally or a common carrier. If we conceptualize the farmers as gaining an easement through the legislation (the right to create a nuisance), that easement, too, is privately owned.38

One could also imagine that courts hostile to regulations will choose, going forward, to enjoin regulations that interfere with property rights whose value is not seen as commensurable with money (or perhaps merely extraordinarily difficult to compute).39 For instance, if the shopping center owners in cases like PruneYard were bothered above all by being forced “to use their own property” to help those they find morally or politically repugnant to spread their message, a court might find that compensation grounded simply in the decline in the market value of the property caused by the presence of unwanted political speakers did not really meet the legitimate interests of those whose property would be taken, and that the only way of vindicating those interests would be to enjoin the regulatory taking entirely.40

III.     Which Economic Losses Should Be Compensated?

If we assume that the access-mandate constitutes a taking and that it will not be enjoined but permitted so long as the state provides just compensation for the regulatory taking, how should we measure just compensation? In his dissent, Justice Breyer noted that the majority did not address the remedies issue but stated that on remand, “California should have the choice of foreclosing injunctive relief by providing compensation.”41

But Justice Breyer did not address the most critical conceptual question the lower courts must face if addressing the compensation issue. If, as is almost surely the case, the decline in the market value of the property resulting from the regulation comes in part (or almost in whole) from the fact that the regulation makes the owner more vulnerable to what employers/owners perceive as profit-reducing unionization,42 should the owner be compensated for the entire economic loss, or is the just compensation due to an owner only for some narrower set of losses that the prohibition on uncompensated takings is suited to protect against?43 Can we distinguish between non-compensable economic losses and compensable ones? If the owners’ real complaint here is that the state is facilitating union organizing, is the complaint any different than it would be if they had challenged regulations that had no relationship to real property, each of which would have been adjudicated under far different legal standards? If an employer whose employees worked off-site is mandated to share contact information for all workers eligible to vote in a certification election with union organizers, that might or might not be legally problematic (it might be troubling because we might think the workers merit legal redress for their loss of privacy). But it would certainly not be problematic because the regulation breached the owners’ purportedly sacrosanct right to exclude physically or block appropriations. And, if we compensate owners for the precise same injury that they would suffer if forced to share email lists when they do not get compensation for whatever economic injury that unionization-facilitating regulation may cause, we should rightly worry that we are adjudicating a claim that “belongs” in the bucket of assessing regulations that facilitate what the state sees as fair union certification battles in a bucket that has little or nothing to do with the injury they actually suffer.

In thinking about the potential mismatch between injury level and injury type, it is tremendously instructive to consider Desnick v. American Broadcasting Cos.44 In the case, the plaintiff ophthalmic clinic (and several clinic employees) sued the defendant TV reporters for trespass, arguing that they assented to the reporters’ entry into their establishment only because the reporters misrepresented their intentions (which were predominantly to expose the clinic for doing unneeded cataract surgery on Medicare-eligible patients).45 The key to understanding Judge Posner’s dismissal of the trespass claim is that one must, in assessing the propriety of granting a trespass remedy, look not to the generic features of trespass but to the legally cognizable interests that trespass law is bound to protect. Posner acknowledges that a defendant may well be a trespasser if he elicits assent (what he calls “express consent”) to his presence on the plaintiff’s property by misrepresenting his intentions,46 but emphasizes that an action in trespass should be used only to vindicate a particular narrower set of interests, not the full panoply of economic losses that the putative trespass may have facilitated.47 The real injury in this case to the plaintiffs was the injury they incurred because the report on their activities damaged their reputation (and perhaps subjected them to criminal investigation or civil suit). But that injury, though economically substantial, must be adjudicated according to the fairly elaborate defamation rules we have collectively established to deal with reputation-damaging conduct.48

Desnick may be an administratively easier case to handle than CPN because Posner readily finds that the plaintiff sustained no damages that trespass law is designed to protect against and thus dismisses the trespass claim entirely.49 But there is every reason to believe that Judge Posner would have thought it appropriate to assess damages for trespass that made no reference to the losses that occurred because of the trespass-facilitated gathering and publication of reputation-damaging content had he believed there were in fact some trespass damages. The task in CPN might well be more administratively complex because it seems most credible to believe that some of the losses the owners experience are properly compensable because they are the sort of protect-against-property-intrusion losses that takings law is indeed designed to protect against, while other economic losses are losses that arise from increasing vulnerability to unionization.

Although specifying which losses an owner bears are compensable and which are not when all we may most readily observe is that the value of the owner’s interests have diminished may be difficult, it is a task courts face in other settings. For instance, in fair use cases, courts believe themselves capable of distinguishing injuries that the copyright regime is designed to protect against from losses that should be adjudicated under a distinct set of legal rules in situations in which the copyright holding plaintiff arguably sustains both sorts of losses.50 The fourth factor in determining whether the defendant has made a fair use of the plaintiff’s copyrighted work under § 107 of the 1976 Copyright Act demands that we attend to the (economic) impact that the infringing fair user’s work will have on the market for or value of the copyrighted work.51 But in many cases in which a putative fair user appropriates a significant portion of the copyrighted work to produce a parody, the copyright holder could be economically damaged both because people may treat the parody as a substitute for the original and because the parody, a form of critique of the copyrighted work, makes potential buyers of the copyrighted work disdain it. Copyright law protects against the injuries from market substitution for the original or suppression of the market for derivative works—in fact, the prototypical copyright violation consists of simply reproducing the copyrighted work and selling it at the (low) cost of reproduction, undercutting the copyright holder’s ability to charge monopoly prices—but does not protect against what might be more significant economic losses that occur because the copyrighted work is seen by consumers as less desirable once they have confronted the critical parody.52 Thus, in SunTrust Bank,53 injuries arising from possible market substitution or suppression of the derivative market would be cognizable in determining whether the appropriation of significant elements of Gone With the Wind by the author of The Wind Done Gone was or was not a fair use of the appropriated elements, but the suppression of demand for Gone With the Wind that might result from the critique of the book’s sentimentalization of slavery and the white planter class would not be.54 Again, whatever protections a copyright holder does or does not have against the economic injuries that arise from effective critique must be judged in accord with the (highly speaker-protective) regime governing defamation and First Amendment-protected speech.

But consider cases in which we determine that both market substitution and effective critique economic effects are present: perhaps most typically, this might occur with parodies of songs by artists like Weird Al Yankovic which are sufficiently well-produced musical reproductions of the parodied songs that some consumers would find it duplicative to buy the original once they have purchased the parody. A court evaluating a fair use claim in such cases cannot merely look at the aggregate impact of the defendant’s work on the plaintiff’s economic interest but must do its best to determine if the losses attributable to market substitution standing alone are sufficient to (help) defeat the fair use claim. To do so of course requires disaggregating the losses in just the same way one might do in Desnick and must almost surely do in CPN.

In CPN, the losses attributable to increased vulnerability to unionization should be adjudicated simply as an aspect of the (state or federal) regime designed to ensure fair contests over unionization, a regime that frequently increases employer vulnerability to unionization, in the same way that Desnick’s substantial economic losses should be adjudicated under defamation law and the copyright holder’s reputational losses under critique-protective First Amendment/defamation regimes. It is possible of course that we would decide that the “vulnerability” losses that result from forcing physical access are less tolerable or reasonable for employers to bear than equivalent economic losses that arise from other requirements that may aid unionization efforts (e.g. requirements that employers not give anti-unionization speeches to “captive audiences” of employees forced to attend the speeches within twenty-four hours of a union election;55 requirements that employers share names and contact information for employees who will vote on unionization).56

I largely set aside a point that might well be determinative for lower courts in CPN: just compensation law across the board is unreceptive to claims of consequential losses that do not arise directly from the fact that the property owner has lost a generic property interest but arise instead from the higher losses that result from the fact that he had made a particular use of his property right. Losses are typically measured by reference to the objective losses that most owners of the property right would sustain (and these are what the government gained when it appropriated the right) rather than the subjective losses borne by a particular owner.57

When an owner raises concerns specific to takings law access requirements (e.g., hedonic losses that arise from compromised privacy; economic losses arising from diminished ability to charge potential customers for access; hedonic and/or economic losses that arise from increased congestion), she should be compensated under Fifth Amendment standards.58 When a taking is needed to facilitate the establishment of a profit-dampening regulatory scheme (as this one is simply part of a scheme of regulating managerial prerogatives to dampen potentially pro-union sentiments), the losses that result from the regulatory scheme should be adjudicated according to a range of standards we must develop to deal with that regulatory matter. I should reiterate a point I made earlier in a different context on the state’s need to “take” property to meet purely regulatory goals because it is germane here59: Had the government simply seized some of the nursery owner’s property that the union organizers in fact used and then granted them access to that condemned land, it would simply have paid for the sliver it seized (without regard to the potential lost profits that unionization might cause).60 But that form of property appropriation would not have been efficacious because it would not have ensured that the organizers had access to workers if the employer, after the condemnation, kept the workers physically separated from the spot the state had seized and then allowed organizers to use. The (non-appropriative) add-on regulation needed to meet the state’s ends would have forbidden employer limitations on worker/organizer contact would plainly have been assessed (in taking terms) under a deferential Penn Central use regulation test and, more pointedly, be judged as part of a regime regulating union organizing.

What is the best measure of the Fifth Amendment losses? Professor Lee Fennell proposes that the taking of what amounts to a rental of a portion of the land for part of the year for use by the organizers (or perhaps an easement granting third party access to a relatively small strip of the nursery’s land) cannot merit more compensation than taking this rental interest in the same small strip would merit.61 She further notes that if that is the case, the compensation ought to be relatively trivial: the cost of the nursery land per acre suggests that the government “took” a property interest worth no more than five dollars per year.62

Professor Fennell’s general claim—an easement over a strip of land or a rental of the land cannot be worth more than the interest in that amount of land would be worth—is unconvincing. A hypothetical farmer might well require much more to sell an easement running right next to her house, or to rent that particular strip, where access holders would interfere with her privacy interests, than she would require to sell the amount of land covered by the easement or rental at the outer edge of her property. But Professor Fennell is clearly on to something. She is coming close to stating the same kind of point that I am emphasizing here, albeit in a way I find less satisfactory: The hypothetical farmer is entitled to compensation for the grant of an easement or leasehold interest that exceeds the value of the acreage covered by the grant only because the taking deprives her of a privacy interest that takings law is in fact suited to deal with.

There is a counterargument that the owner might make that Professor Fennell does not adequately attend to.63 One of the reasons owners want to retain the right to deny access—and one of the reasons that they would charge more to surrender the right to control access—is that they want to be able to exclude those (like union organizers) who will impact their profits more than generic access-seekers would. But, at core, this misses the point of the California access requirement, which is simply to help establish a regulatory scheme in which the right to dole out access in that way is simply not a stick in the bundle of exclusion rights that the nursery owner retains.

Reconsider the question of whether landlords in Loretto were entitled to substantial compensation, as Richard Epstein argued, because after the state mandated cable company access, they could no longer sell access rights to the cable company.64 But the whole point of mandating cable company access is to deprive a landlord of the ability to take advantage of its natural monopoly over access to cable customers in order to divide profits from cable service with the cable company.65 The state could certainly have regulated the price at which sales of access occurred, and this price regulation would be subject to deferential review of whether the price control itself constituted a taking.66 Because the competitive price of allowing access to one’s tenants is its zero marginal cost (and that may well be the optimal price a regulator would set), a simple price control scheme without an access requirement (i.e. demanding that there be a contract at some price, which proves to be the regulated price of zero) is obviously inefficacious: no sales contracts whose price terms would be subject to deferentially reviewed regulation would be entered into. But what we also see is that the landlord was not deprived of the ability to charge a monopoly price because he never had that power in a reasonable regulatory regime. We should judge whether the regulatory deprivation of the right to charge a high price that takes advantage of the natural monopoly is a taking—it is not a close question under existing law—but we cannot measure the just compensation that is owed as a result of the per se taking of the exclusion right by noting that had the taking not occurred, the owner would have exercised his exclusion right to increase the value of his holdings in ways that he is simply not entitled to.

Conclusion

In reflecting on Cedar Point Nursery, there is a significant, familiar jurisprudential point to be made. We should read rights purposively. Plaintiffs can vindicate rights using trespass law only when doing so would meet the purposes we ascribe to trespass law. Owners merit compensation under takings law only if doing so meets the purposes we ascribe to protecting an owner against takings. There is also very practical point here: We should not measure the compensation that plaintiffs merit by asking whether they would have sustained fewer economic losses absent some rights violation. We should look instead to measure only the losses we seek to avoid by establishing the right.

What we should learn from Desnick is that the fact that the plaintiff might not have sustained reputational losses absent a trespass that gave the trespassers access to reputation-damaging information does not mean that the damages for trespass should incorporate the damages for reputational losses. This is particularly vital to note because the limitations on what damages can and cannot be assessed for reputational losses given existing defamation doctrine are less protective of the plaintiff than a rule that gave a trespass plaintiff compensation for all economic losses facilitated by the trespass would be. Trespass law must stay in its lane.

We must similarly keep takings law in its lane. In CPN, the fact that the nursery owners might have had the ability to suppress what they see as profit-dampening unionization efforts absent the taking does not mean they are entitled to be compensated for the loss of the ability to suppress unionization. Just as we must assess reputation-damaging statements under the law of defamation, we must deal with the validity of laws limiting the capacity to suppress unionization efforts in their own terms. What the owners in CPN are entitled to is compensation for the loss of the rights takings law protects against—in cases like this of temporary access mandates, losses that inhere in having to share use of a portion of the property with others. If the owners’ losses are occasioned not by the taking but solely by their increased vulnerability to unionization, though, they deserve no compensation at all.

 


* James C. Gaither Professor of Law and Vice Dean at Stanford Law School. Thanks to Pam Karlan for helpful comments on an earlier draft.