Reforming Informed Consent to Include Comprehension: A Proposal to Promote Equity in Medical Decision-Making

Introduction

The ethical goals of the legal doctrine of informed consent are lofty. The law requires that clinicians explain the risks, benefits, and alternatives of proposed treatments to patients, and to respect patient autonomy through voluntary, informed medical decisions aligned with individual values and preferences. Yet in practice, patients often struggle to comprehend the risks and alternatives of a proposed medical intervention.1 Since investigators began analyzing the sufficiency of informed consent, it has been recognized that the current rules, which focus solely on clinical disclosures, are inadequate in addressing disparities associated with education, race/ethnicity, and age.2

Health literacy gaps and power differentials between doctors and patients make true comprehension of health information elusive for vulnerable groups.3 Consent documents laden with dense technical and numerical data are often indecipherable.4 Negative healthcare encounters, cultural factors, and individual and community experiences of exploitation and racism create distrust among marginalized groups who have been systemically denied access to medical decision-making and medical education.5

Consequently, despite technically “adequate” disclosures under the legal doctrine of informed consent, patients may consent to major procedures with little substantive grasp of the risks. This undermines decision-making autonomy, reduces consent to a hollow formality, and fails to facilitate truly educated, empowered choices.

I. Reforming Informed Consent Law to Include a Comprehension Element

Shifting the law’s emphasis from disclosures alone to disclosure and comprehension will better align the ethical goals of informed consent with the legal rules that govern it.6 Scholars in the medical and ethics fields have consistently advocated for a new comprehension-based standard that better reflects the ethical principles and goals of informed consent7—namely, recognizing that informed consent “relies on patients understanding the information they are given to inform their decision.”8 Significantly, the law could be reformed to reflect this standard. To address inequalities in the informed consent process, the law should reduce emphasis on technical disclosure requirements and strengthen focus on patient comprehension. Thus, in addition to mandated disclosures, the physician’s duty to the patient must include assurance of patient comprehension of the risks, benefits, and alternatives of the proposed intervention.9

In other words, when we assess whether a patient agreed to a particular intervention, we need to know what the patient understood. The court in the seminal 1972 decision Canterbury v. Spence held that “[t]rue consent to what happens to one’s self is the informed exercise of a choice, and that entails the opportunity to evaluate knowledgeably the options available and the risks attendant upon each.”10 Choice cannot be effectuated in the absence of understanding of the implications and weight of those choices. Thus, disclosures alone cannot ensure that medical decision making is a true expression of self-determination.

Adopting a new rule for clinical informed consent would incentivize clinicians to take greater care, confirming patient understanding by using validated strategies such as physician decision aids,11 increasing the use of technology in the informed consent process,12 “repeat back”/“teach back” techniques,13 and the “best case/worst case” approach.14 Admittedly, comprehension can be complex to reliably measure. But the current legal rule’s efficiency belies the law’s ability to facilitate better decisions and results in over-disclosure of information in efforts to avoid liability (which in turn can lead to less comprehension as patients are overwhelmed with information). Although incorporating a comprehension element in the legal doctrine of informed consent involves challenges, doing so reflects a commitment to patient-centric reform where empowerment through understanding takes priority over administrative efficiency.15 If informed consent is to be more than an empty formality, prioritizing comprehension is essential. Emerging empirical research on measuring understanding can help develop flexible legal standards for adequate comprehension.

Moreover, establishing a rule for comprehension that looks to the individual patient’s understanding respects the fact that patient preferences are personal and may be idiosyncratic. No matter what the outcome, it is the patient who will bear its burden.

II. The Potential to Reduce Health Disparities

This proposal has the primary goal of improving informed consent writ large, but has the important potential benefit of mitigating disparities in medical care. Effective physician-patient communication is linked with improved patient health outcomes.16 But deficiencies in physician-patient communication may contribute to health care disparities.17 As a result of discrepancies in health care literacy and education status,18 communication barriers,19 bias,20 and distrust,21 physician-patient communications among historically marginalized populations have suffered. For example, Black patients rate visits with physicians as significantly less participatory than whites, particularly where there is not racial/ethnic concordance.22

Requiring clinicians to assess patient comprehension during the informed consent process addresses these systemic disadvantages directly. It provides underserved communities targeted support in comprehending risks and weighing alternatives to make choices aligned with their values and preferences. Alongside broader equity efforts, informed consent discussions that emphasize comprehension further patient autonomy by empowering patients with the knowledge needed for informed decision-making. Maintaining formulaic consent rituals that fail the disadvantaged seems ethically untenable. Introducing a comprehension element in the informed consent process is a step toward fixing a system that enables inequities cloaked in hollow disclosure rituals. Shifting the legal requirements for informed consent to add a comprehension element also complements broader initiatives to promote health equity through greater community empowerment, culturally responsive practices, improved health literacy, and increased provider diversity.

III. Comprehension, Patient Choice, and Clinician Agreement

It has been recognized that patient involvement in their care “via negotiation and consensus-seeking” improves patient outcomes.23 When there is conflict between a clinician’s preferred course of treatment and a patient’s choice, quality of care and medical outcomes can suffer. Moreover, physicians are more likely to presume lack of decision-making capacity when patients go against medical advice.24 In other words, while medical ethics “encourages tolerance even towards harmful choices patients make on the basis of their own values,” 25 in practice this is often only true if the plaintiff agrees with the physician’s recommended course of treatment.26 When patients disagree with the physician’s recommendation, the patient’s capacity to consent will be questioned. And, in many cases, patient disagreement with clinical recommendations is more prevalent amongst patients with low literacy levels and patients from minority communities in race/ethnicity discordant physician-patient relationships.27 Oftentimes, such disagreements arise from lack of patient understanding of the risks, benefits, and alternatives of the proposed intervention.28 Thus, comprehension can play a key role when patients make choices that contradict physician recommendations and result in less than favorable outcomes.

At least in scholarly literature, a commonly accepted trope is that informed consent does not require that consent be rational.29 This is a feature, and not a bug, of the current disclosure-focused rule. So long as doctors have fulfilled their legal disclosure requirements, the patient’s consent is sufficient.30 This may result in irrational and illogical agreements (or disagreements) to an intervention. The current legal rule is often justified by reliance on the autonomy principle: patients are allowed to make whatever decision they choose, regardless of whether it is medically justified.31

However, these arguments miss the point. If we knew that the patient understood what the risks, benefits, and alternatives of a proposed intervention were, perhaps we could reduce dissenting decision-making (at least to some extent).32 In other words, if we do not know that the patient actually understood the facts upon which they are basing their decision to accept or reject a proposed intervention, then we cannot know whether the patient’s decision was “irrational,” whether the patient simply did not fully understand the decision they were making, or whether the patient’s decision was based on values and preferences that do not align with clinical medical advice.33 But if we know that patients truly comprehend the decision that they are making, we can put more faith in their decisions (even when they are contrary to clinical advice). Further, with increased comprehension of the risks, benefits, and alternatives of a proposed course of treatment, we may even see more patients agreeing with physician recommendations.34 Patients’ ability to make decisions after they understand the disclosed information may therefore lead to more accord between physician and patient.35

Shifting the focus of our informed consent rule to comprehension could more truly respect individual patient autonomy than the existing rule. Enhancing comprehension lays the groundwork for more informed patient decisions. Holding and acting on rational beliefs may promote autonomy.36 Even if those decisions ultimately still oppose medical advice, they will at least be grounded in a substantive comprehension of the risks and benefits of the proposed intervention. Emphasizing comprehension upholds the ethical goals of informed consent while promoting high-quality, ethical care for diverse populations.

Conclusion

Informed consent cannot fulfill its ethical goals if patients are unable to comprehend the risks, benefits, and alternatives of the proposed intervention when they are disclosed. Whereas unilateral disclosures fulfill the current legal requirements of the doctrine of informed consent, emphasizing comprehension enables patients to evaluate risks and benefits based on their own personal values and preferences. This, in turn, may empower patients and align the law of informed consent with the ethical values of ensuring voluntary, informed decision-making. Beyond being technically told the risks, patients gain the opportunity to meaningfully discuss them with clinicians, thereby reducing historically entrenched power asymmetries. Ensuring patient comprehension in the informed consent process empowers patients to be more collaborative partners in medical decision-making. Ensuring comprehension in consent conversations enhances trust and humanizes patients as partners in their own care, rather than passive recipients of technical disclosures. Reform centered on understanding, rather than rituals, brings informed consent’s realities closer to its ethical aspirations. In doing so, it upholds consent’s role in advancing equitable, patient-focused healthcare.

Centering comprehension in consent laws is a pragmatic, incremental strategy to promote equity. Thus, ensuring patient comprehension in the informed consent process is a first step in establishing more culturally responsive practices, potentially improving patient trust and empowering medical decision-making for historically and systemically marginalized communities.


* Assistant Professor and Co-Director of the Health Law & Policy Institute at the University of Houston Law Center and the Director of Law & Ethics at the MacLean Center for Clinical Medical Ethics at the University of Chicago. Thank you to the Elizabeth D. Rockwell Center on Ethics and Leadership at the Hobby School of Public Affairs, University of Houston, for its support of this work, and to Laurie G. Kahn for her sensitive and thoughtful feedback.