Populism and Constitutionalism: An Essay on Definitions and Their Implications

Introduction

Around the world governments characterized by observers as populist have taken power. Many of their actions have been incompatible with tenets of modern liberalism. This has generated commentary suggesting that populism is itself incompatible with constitutionalism.

This Essay challenges that commentary. We agree that some variants of populism are incompatible with modern liberal constitutionalism but argue that the tension between populism as such and constitutionalism as such, though real, is significantly narrower than much commentary suggests. We begin in Part II by offering “barebones” definitions of populism and constitutionalism so that we can tease out precisely what the tension between them is. Part III turns to case studies of challenges to judicial independence, of the use of referendums, and of innovative methods of determining the public’s views. As with our discussion of defining populism and constitutionalism, here we attempt to identify whether (or the degree to which) the case studies demonstrate a tension between populism and constitutionalism. Our conclusion is that sometimes we can see such a tension and sometimes we cannot, and that the analysis of specific populisms and their policies in relation to constitutionalism must be highly sensitive to context.

Part IV applies the argument to two developments in the United Kingdom: the Brexit referendum and the attempt by Boris Johnson to prorogue Parliament and the ensuing decision by the UK Supreme Court finding the prorogation unlawful. Here our conclusion once again is that analysis of populism’s relation to constitutionalism must be sensitive to context: the referendum was flawed but not in ways that cast a bad light on populism as such, and the prorogation, while perhaps unlawful, was not clearly anti-constitutional.

Overall, we argue against generalized claims about populism as such and constitutionalism as such. There are many populisms and at least a few constitutionalisms, and scholars and observers should direct their attention to the questions posed by specific actions taken by individual populist governments. Sometimes populist governments will act in anti-constitutional ways, and sometimes they will not. We believe that this conclusion is appropriately deflationary.

I. An Overview: Definitions and Barebones Definitions

The contemporary literature on modern populism is filled with claims that populism is in some tension with constitutionalism. Of course we can define both terms in ways that make them incompatible (for example by defining populism as necessarily committed to ethno-nationalism, untrammeled executive power, and a non-pluralist opposition between a unified “People” and cosmopolitan elites, and constitutionalism as necessarily committed to an extremely thick conception of liberal constitutionalism replete with all sorts of rights-guarantees).1 Suppose, though, we started with relatively barebones definitions of each term and then examined the degree to which they are incompatible. That is our strategy here.2 We begin with an inevitably incomplete survey of some definitions of populism offered in the existing literature. We then offer our barebones definitions of populism and constitutionalism, and the real—and perhaps unimportant—conflict between populism and constitutionalism under those definitions. Our theme is this: because populism takes many forms,3 the conflict between populism “as such” and constitutionalism, while real, is narrower than often posited, and sometimes constitutionalism might properly come out the loser in such conflicts.4

A. Definitions of Populism: An Overview

Handbooks, research guides, and companions to populism abound.5 Authors use the term to refer to a large number of political movements, and no agreed-upon definition has yet emerged. Jan-Werner Müller’s formulation is probably the most widely cited: for him, populism is “a particular moralistic imagination of politics, a way of perceiving the political world that sets a morally pure and fully unified—but . . . ultimately fictional—people against elites who are deemed corrupt or in some other way morally inferior.”6 As we describe next, though, other authors attribute other characteristics to populism, and some omit one or more features of Müller’s definition. Our view is that, to use a tired metaphor, populisms may share a family resemblance, but the family is an extended one whose dispersal around the world has produced members who could have little to say to each other at a family reunion.7

We take as our initial texts two articles appearing in a symposium on “Public Law and the New Populism,” published in the International Journal of Constitutional Law (I-CON), a leading journal in the field of comparative constitutional law.8 Because we do not pretend that these articles provide a comprehensive dictionary entry on “populism,” we then turn to a selection of additional articles. Along the way we make some critical comments on each definition, hinting at the components of the barebones definition we offer in the following Section.

Neil Walker supplements Müller’s definition with a related phrase—populists see politics as “involving a binary opposition between ‘two homogeneous and antagonistic camps’”—from another highly cited work, Mudde and Kaltwasser’s “Populism: A Very Short Introduction.”9 Mudde and Kaltwasser’s modification is important because it makes explicit the proposition that populism, in their understanding, is by definition anti-pluralist. Though Müller puts anti-pluralism at the center of his analysis, his presentation, in contrast, could be understood to refer to nearly all forms of political activity by “ordinary” people unified for political purposes only in a project aimed at displacing existing ruling elites with political leaders more attuned to the interests of the people—interests that could in principle vary depending on which groups of ordinary people are most immediately affected by specific policies. The corruption and moral inferiority that Müller sees in populism’s description of ruling elites could, again in principle, be a way of characterizing their failure to take the interests of (a possibly pluralist) “ordinary” population adequately into account.10

Paul Blokker advances a more tentative definition of populism, in large part because he expressly includes left- and right-wing versions within his purview. For him, in populist constitutionalism, “the actual engagement of (different groups of) citizens in society is substituted for by the idea of a united people, represented by the populist leader. The main culprit is identified in corrupt elite rule,” which, he notes earlier, is “detrimental to the common good.”11 Further, populism “tend[s] to deny a strong separation of politics and law and endorse[s] a stronger link between constitutions and the people.”12 Populists criticize “the idea of the law as non-political and neutral,” and “what is perceived as a strong separation between law, on the one hand, and politics and morality on the other.”13 With others, Blokker describes this attitude as “instrumentalism.”14 This makes populists “critical about the strong and independent nature of apex courts, the role and form of judicial review, and the extensive and entrenched nature of individual rights.”15 It “tend[s] to suffer from an exclusionary tendency, which results from the quest for an authentic people, and in practice risk[s] sliding into either authoritarian or ‘leaderist’-plebiscitarian modes.”16 Finally, Blokker asserts that “majoritarianism” is a characteristic feature of populism, and that populism involves “a political appeal to the people, and a claim to legitimacy that rests on the democratic ideology of popular sovereignty and majority rule.”17

As this last quotation suggests, we believe that much of what Blokker described as characteristic of populism is more accurately described as characteristic of democratic politics and of law itself. We can imagine a view of politics as founded on natural law or something similar, but most democratic theorists, we believe, agree that democracy ultimately “rests on” some version of an “ideology of popular sovereignty.”18 Similarly with majoritarianism: a well-known result in social/public choice theory shows that majoritarianism is the only voting rule that generates stable policies (as long as preferences are stable).19 And there is a jurisprudential defense of an instrumentalist view of law rooted not only in Carl Schmitt’s work, to which Blokker alludes,20 but also in the American Legal Realist tradition and its descendant Critical Legal Studies. The Realists and their successors argued that in the end, though not necessarily proximately, law was always instrumental. Avant la lettre, they were critical of aggressive forms of constitutional review and skeptical about claims that general guarantees of individual rights generated specific outcomes in controversial cases.21 We think it worth entertaining the view that populists have a better understanding of law as such, that is, as ultimately instrumental, than their critics.

As with Mudde and Kaltwasser, for Blokker what appears to single out populism from other forms of political activity by ordinary people, then, is a principled anti-pluralism. And here we note that one regime often described as populist, Bolivia under Evo Morales, promoted a constitution that expressly described the nation as “plurinational,” in implicit contrast to the prior (liberal?) constitutional regime that was exclusionary.22 Hannah Arendt famously argued that the liberal revolutions of the eighteenth and nineteenth century transformed subjects into citizens, that this elimination of formal exclusions from citizenship opened up what she called the “social question” of effective but informal exclusions, and that later revolutions (which she criticized) sought to resolve the social question.23 On this view, existing liberal constitutional regimes are in practice exclusionary (anti-pluralist, in a sense), and populism can be inclusionary.

We agree that some populist movements have the characteristics described by Müller, Mudde and Kaltwasser, Walker, and Blokker.24 But, as Robert Howse writes in the I-CON symposium, “[t]he populist label is a form of ‘othering’ that eschews serious engagement with those who see more promise than peril in today’s disruptive politics,” and that it is often attached to give “a pejorative cast on disruptive democratic politics of any sort that challenges elitist liberal democracy.”25 He also observes that “[t]he answer, ‘that’s just . . . how we define populism’ . . . seem[s] thoroughly question-begging.”26 We turn now to our barebones definitions, first of populism and then of constitutionalism, with the aim of determining whether or to what extent populism as we define it is inconsistent with constitutionalism.

B. Barebones Populism and Constitutionalism

Begin with populism. In our barebones definition populism is a theory of political choice according to which the reliably determined views of a current majority of citizens on any issue dictate policy until a later majority of citizens chooses, again through a method that reliably identifies current preferences, to alter the policy.27 In addition, as already indicated, populism differs from mere majoritarianism in its emphasis on the role of “ordinary” people in forming majorities, as against “elites.”28 Drawing on a long sociological tradition,29 populism understands elites to be groups, defined variously by class position, ethnicity, religion, or other characteristics (including ideological orientations), who have become entrenched in a nation’s governing structure.

The first key concept here is that the range of policy choice is unrestricted: Populist decision-making can deal with tax policy or (in contrast to thick specifications) human rights policy or anything else. Nothing is taken off the table for decision by majorities (again, subject to the requirement that the majority’s preferences be reliably determined).

The second key concept is that of reliable determination. This is a substantive criterion, not a procedural one. Some procedures might make us more confident that the determination is more reliable than the determination by other procedures. Notably, though, decisions taken by bodies (“legislatures”) comprised of representatives elected on general party platforms are not necessarily more reliable than those taken through direct consultation with the citizenry through a referendum.30 And, indeed, sometimes a system of informal consultations might be as reliable as a formal vote for parties with general platforms.31

Finally, the barebones definition allows for the possibility that “the majority” is a fluid concept, shifting as different policy issues come to the fore. On each issue political leaders will claim to be speaking for “the People,” and sometimes issues will cluster in ways that allow political leaders to assemble a reasonably comprehensive political platform. In some sense, even a pluralist majority will stand in opposition to those who oppose the majority on a range of issues. But, on the barebones definition, this simply describes how majoritarian politics operates; it is not a definition of social reality external to politics. For populists, opposition to the policies favored by a majority of ordinary people reflects the interest of entrenched elites in maintaining their privileged position, not a genuine concern that the proposed policies are bad for ordinary people themselves.

A reliable determination of preferences does require mechanisms for voicing disagreement with policy proposals (“free expression” in a barebones sense). Further, those who disagree with a policy proposal, or with an entire array of proposals, are met with efforts to persuade rather than with force.32

Next, consider our barebones definition of constitutionalism. It too has several key components. First, the policy space is divided into two domains. In one, decisions are taken according to roughly majoritarian procedural rules defined in the constitution (the “mere policy” domain). In the other (the “rights” domain), certain substantive decisions—identified in the constitution—cannot be made pursuant to the rules governing the policy domain.33 Decisions in this domain can be made after those rules are altered by an amendment process requiring more than that used in the policy domain (typically, some sort of formal supermajority requirement).

Second, as already indicated, rules regulate how policy is to be determined within the policy domain. Those rules are typically designed to ensure that when new policy is adopted (enacted by a legislature or promulgated by an executive), it probably has the support of a current majority of citizens. But, in the barebones conception of constitutionalism the rules rather than the support by the citizenry matters. In particular, the “mere” fact that according to some reliable indicators of current popular will a majority prefers that policy be changed is not enough: Policy change can occur only through using the prescribed processes. Typically—though not universally—the prescribed processes contain “veto gates,” that is places where those with less than majority support can block movement toward a policy’s adoption.

Third, disputes will inevitably arise about the application of enacted laws in individual cases. Barebones constitutionalism requires that those disputes be resolved with reference to law, which in turn requires that the judges deciding them orient themselves to law rather than to politics—or more precisely, orient themselves to politics only to the degree that the law itself requires them to do so (the instrumentalism implicit in law, as we suggested above).34

We pause to note that barebones constitutionalism does not require judicial resolution of disputes about whether enacted statutes are consistent with the nation’s constitution (and so does not require that there be independent constitutional courts at all). What recent theorists have labeled “political constitutionalism,” in which constitutional limits on legislative power are enforced through political mechanisms, is entirely consistent with barebones constitutionalism.35

On these barebones definitions populism and constitutionalism do conflict. Constitutionalism restricts the range of policies as to which majoritarian preferences can prevail, and even within the “mere policy” domain its procedural rules can impede the adoption of policies (not affecting “rights”) that majorities prefer. Consider a nation whose constitution entrenches a bicameral legislature, with the lower house elected every three years by proportional representation in the nation as a whole and an upper house elected every six years by plurality voting in each province. It is not unimaginable that legislation supported by a national majority would be blocked by the upper house either for several years or even permanently.

The next question, though, is whether the fact that populism and constitutionalism conflict in these ways is an argument against populism or, instead, an argument against constitutionalism. Consider for example the possibility that a populist party’s major policy proposal is a substantial increase in the taxes paid by the extremely wealthy. We can of course have substantive discussions of whether such a proposal is a sound one, and if the people reject it no populist could reasonably complain. But, if the populist party prevails and its proposal is blocked at one of the procedural veto gates, the argument for constitutionalism over populism is not obviously the better one.36

Constitutionalism’s purely procedural requirements can operate within the “mere policy” domain to block populist policies with majority support (reliably determined in some manner independent of those procedural requirements). Perhaps some purely procedural requirements have strong normative justifications. Some defend bicameralism on the ground that it improves the quality of legislation, for example. Some defend it on the ground that different bases for representation obstruct legislation that might be inconsistent with aspects of national identity reflected in those different bases. If these normative claims are accepted, constitutionalism may be an argument against populism.

What, though, of the “rights” domain? Here what matters is whether the rights singled out are thinly or thickly specified. A thinly specified right is identified in the constitution at a rather high level of generality (“freedom of expression” or “equality”); increasingly thick specifications give increasingly detailed content to the rights. Thicker specifications remove more choice (with respect to rights) from the domain in which (under populism’s first component) reliably determined preferences prevail and (under constitutionalism’s procedural version) preferences that are procedurally validated prevail. Thicker rights-specifications set populism against constitutions with thick specifications (though they also set such constitutions against constitutionalism’s commitment to validation of policy choice by adherence to procedural rules).37

It is hardly obvious that (all) rights within the rights domain should be thickly specified. Perhaps the only right as to which there is a consensus on relatively thick specification is the right against torture. Others such as freedom of expression are (typically) thinly specified. And thin specifications can substantially reduce the tension between populism and constitutionalism.

Consider the example of freedom of expression. Reasonable people can disagree over a host of questions about specifications: Does banning hate speech violate the (thinly defined) right of free expression? If some bans on hate speech do not do so, under what circumstances will a statute banning hate speech be drafted in terms that do not pose a danger to freedom of expression? Another example: speech—even about core political matters—can sometimes cause social harm (from “mere” law violation when speech critical of an enacted policy induces people to refuse to comply with that policy, through, and up to, quite violent resistance to the government generally (“seditious speech” leading to attempted revolution)). How tight must the causal connection be between the speech and the ensuing harm (a tendency to cause harm, presenting a clear and present danger of harm, inciting imminent action that will cause harm)?

Suppose a (populist-governed) nation has a constitution with thinly specified rights and adopts a rights-related policy that is inconsistent with thickly specified rights. On the barebones conceptions we see no conflict between populism and constitutionalism—as long as the populist policy is within the range of reasonable disagreement about the proper specification of the right in question.

There are two complications here. The smaller one lies in defining what counts as a reasonable disagreement over specification. “Reasonableness” must be given a generous definition lest the distinction between thin and thick specifications collapse.38 The larger difficulty is that specifications that are reasonable when seen in isolation or outside the precise political context within which they are adopted and implemented might be unreasonable in that context. Kim Lane Scheppele has identified the “frankenstate,” an authoritarian regime composed of elements extracted from non-authoritarian systems, where those elements constrain government, and stitched together in a way that leaves the government effectively unconstrained.39 The mechanism by which these elements, reasonable specifications in the abstract, become unreasonable in the aggregate is this: (1) In Nation A, element X constrains government because of its interaction with element Z; (2) in Nation B, element Y constrains because of its interaction with element not-Z; (3) X, Y, Z, and —importantly—not-Z are all reasonable specifications of the relevant constitutional provisions; but (4) combining element X with element not-Z leaves the government unconstrained. Under these conditions we will indeed find a conflict between constitutionalism and that particular brand of populism.

That, though, is quite different from finding a general conflict between constitutionalism and populism. And that, ultimately, is our critique of the argument that constitutionalism and populism conflict. We ought to criticize specific populisms when they are inconsistent with constitutionalism, but on the barebones definitions we should not find a general conflict. Or, put another way, the argument that constitutionalism and populism conflict is too often a concealed way of criticizing specific regimes—and that form of criticism can slop over into criticism of other populist regimes that are consistent with constitutionalism in the barebones definition.

II. Deepening the Argument

In this Part we examine several topics that have provoked discussions about the conflict between populism and constitutionalism. In the terms introduced above, three deal with the procedural dimension of constitutionalism—modifications of procedural mechanisms that define judicial independence (primarily on connection with constitutional courts), the use of referendums to determine policy (displacing a legislative decision with respect to the subjects of the referendums), and what we call creative populist institutions for determining popular policy preferences. The order of our presentation reflects our judgment that policies affecting the courts are the most likely to challenge constitutionalism, that referendums can sometimes raise questions about the reliability of the outcomes in reflecting popular preferences, and that the creative devices we describe are unlikely to be inconsistent with barebones constitutionalism and even with notions of constitutionalism that have more flesh on the bones. The final discussion deals briefly with the rights-domain.

Throughout, though more explicitly in the final one, we rely on the distinction we have introduced between thick and thin specifications of structures and rights. And, as throughout, our theme is that resolving questions about conflicts between populism and constitutionalism requires attention to actual local circumstances; it cannot be done wholesale on the conceptual level.

A. Judicial Independence

We argued above that barebones constitutionalism requires judicial resolution of disputes over the implementation of enacted legislation pursuant to law rather than “mere” politics, though we stress that the distinction between law and politics is sometimes thin. Judicial independence (from “mere” politics) is the institutional mechanism for securing that form of resolution. Constitutions design that mechanism in many ways, ranging from complete discretion in the executive to appointment of judges by judges themselves.40 There are, that is, numerous institutional specifications for mechanisms designed to secure judicial independence.

Populists dissatisfied with the performance of their nation’s constitutional courts sometimes propose to change from one mechanism to another. These proposals are often characterized as “assaults” on judicial independence. It should be clear, though, that a simple change from one mechanism to another is not necessarily such an assault: sometimes the changes are defensible as improvements in a system that in operation has proven flawed, sometimes they are defensible as the substitution of one mechanism for another that has simply become politically unpopular.

We next provide brief case studies from India, Israel, and Poland of populist-motivated changes in the mechanisms for judicial appointment and removal to expose the difficulties associated with determining when a change is better described as an assault than as an improvement or neutral alternative. In each case the alterations were largely motivated by disagreement with important constitutional court decisions. We think it is more difficult to determine, though, whether those motivations produced new mechanisms that actually threatened judicial independence.

For India, we think it quite difficult to see an assault rather than an alternative, though we concede that observers more closely attuned than we are to local politics might conclude otherwise.41 For Israel, we think the proposals sought to change outcomes the Supreme Court would reach and so were in some sense an assault on judicial independence, though sometimes the outcomes were themselves choices by the Supreme Court to reject reasonable specifications of constitutional rights. And for Poland, we think the answer is unequivocal: the changes were designed for, and have largely accomplished, the subordination of law to politics—a true assault on judicial independence.

1. India

The Indian Constitution provides that the President appoints Supreme Court justices “after consultation with such of the Judges of the Supreme Court and of the High Courts in the States as the President may deem necessary for the purpose.”42 Several major decisions interpreting this provision produced a requirement that the President appoint justices recommended by the “collegium”—basically, a small council of senior Supreme Court justices.43 The court’s decisions defended this self-perpetuating feature as essential to achieve the degree of judicial independence the constitution required. It was obviously in some tension with standard views of constitutionalism that require some degree of democratic accountability in the appointment process, particularly because the President of India, though elected, is a typical “head of state” rather than “head of government.” Further, the collegium’s decision-making processes are quite opaque; insiders can sometimes discern what they think are the standards the collegium uses—including demographic and geographic representativeness—but with no real confidence about how those standards are applied in specific appointments.44

The “democratic deficit” in the appointment process, perhaps only modest, is augmented by other features of the Supreme Court’s functioning. The Supreme Court is large, currently with thirty-four members. Ordinarily the court sits in panels of three to five, the number and the members chosen by the Chief Justice. In important cases the Chief Justice can convene a large panel of five or more judges.45 This arrangement means that outcomes can vary widely depending on which judges sit on (or are chosen to sit on) the larger benches. Inevitably, judgments attract political criticism from one or another side of the political spectrum, taking the form of assertions that the bench in question decided with reference to politics rather than law.46

In 2014 Narendra Modi of the Bharatiya Janata Party (BJP) became prime minister when his party won a majority in the lower house.47 The BJP was a Hindu-nationalist party. In 1994 the Supreme Court addressed the nation’s constitutional commitment to secularism in the course of several opinions dealing with presidential decrees dismissing BJP-led governments in three state governments.48 The opinions embedded secularism in the constitution’s “basic structure,” meaning that even a constitutional amendment could not alter that commitment. The BJP took this to threaten its ability to advance important parts of its political agenda, even though the force of the court’s opinions was weakened by subsequent cases defining “Hindutva,” a Hindu-focused ideology to which the BJP was itself committed, as consistent with secularism.49

Early in its tenure the Modi government introduced and a nearly unanimous parliament enacted a constitutional amendment that altered the method of judicial appointment.50 The amendment created a judicial appointment commission that in general conformed to international standards for such commissions; its members were to be the Chief Justice, two other justices, the minister of justice, and two “eminent persons” nominated by a committee of the Chief Justice, the Prime Minister, and the leader of the opposition (or, as has been the case when there is no official opposition party, the leader of the largest single opposition party). A statute that was part of the amendment “package deal” specified that no one could be recommended by the commission if two members voted against the candidate.51

The Supreme Court held this constitutional amendment to be an unconstitutional violation of the judicial independence required by the nation’s “basic structure.”52 The individual opinions in the case are long and detailed.53 The guiding principle appears to be that judicial independence requires that judges have a primary or perhaps dominant role in judicial appointments. That principle generates two more particularized concerns. First, exactly half of the commission’s membership were judges. This meant that the judges could block the appointment of nominees who were in their judgment unqualified, but they could not guarantee the appointment of candidates who they deemed the most suitable.54 Second, the Minister of Justice provided counsel in cases involving the government, that is, in a large swathe of the Court’s jurisdiction. That meant that the Minister would have an institutional interest in pushing through the appointment of government-friendly judges.55

The Indian judicial appointment commission was not that distinctive from other commissions around the world.56 Many include the Minister of Justice, a point of particular concern to the Indian Court.57 The Indian commission would have been smaller than many commissions,58 which suggests that the Justice Minister might have had an outsized role, and one might worry as well about the Prime Minister’s influence in choosing the “eminent persons” to sit on the commission. Still, these are, we think, thin reeds on which to rest the powerful weapon provided by the “basic structure” doctrine.59 This is especially so because of widespread and seemingly well-founded concern that the collegium process as it had come to operate was quite flawed, and even when, as we concede, the constitutional amendment might well have been motivated by disagreement with important Supreme Court decisions. There appear to have been sound good-government reasons for altering the collegium process, and the judicial appointments commission appears to have been an improvement over that process even if not perfect. It is not clear to us that the fact that there were crass political motivations underlying the reform should strongly overcome the force of those two factors.60

The key difficulty with identifying court reforms motivated by disagreement with court decisions as assaults on the judiciary is this: disagreement with court decisions can arise not from the view that the courts ought to be more responsive to public sentiment—from a desire to subordinate law to politics—but rather from the view that the court decisions were legally erroneous or, less provocatively, from the view that the court mistakenly rejected as unconstitutional statutes (and constitutional amendments) that were consistent with some reasonable interpretations of the relevant constitutional terms and (an important addition) that ordinary democratic theory should counsel judges to accept legislative decisions supported by such reasonable interpretations.61

2. Israel

For several decades the Supreme Court of Israel has been one of the leading institutions in the nation articulating and to some extent making legally enforceable views associated with Israel’s more secular, liberal, and European-origin population. During that period politics—in the legislature and so in the prime ministry and executive cabinet—has been controlled in large part by more conservative, more religious, and Sephardic and Russian-origin demographic groups. That political control has been strong but not overwhelming, and the Supreme Court has been able largely to sustain its more liberal and secular orientation, though with some modifications around the edges.62 The court’s role became politically contentious after what Israelis describe as the “Constitutional Revolution” inaugurated by adoption in 1992 of two new Basic Laws, the first such laws to deal with fundamental rights. The Supreme Court took their enactment to justify its adoption of a strong principle of constitutional review of legislation.63 The court had already become known as “activist” through its aggressive use of administrative review and “subconstitutional law” such as rights-respecting statutory interpretation, but the Constitutional Revolution consolidated the Court’s and the public’s understanding of its role.

Conservative political forces in the Likud Party and in coalition governments made Supreme Court reform an item on their political agenda, though, it is important to note, court reform while always on the agenda was never a high political priority. Proposals for reform took various forms, and we focus solely on one dealing with changing the mechanism of appointment to the Supreme Court.

Israel’s Basic Law: The Judiciary is the relevant “constitutional” document.64 Enacted in 1984, that law creates a judicial selection committee of nine members: three justices of the Supreme Court including its President (chief justice), the Minister of Justice and another government minister, two members of the legislature elected by it (one of whom is by tradition not a member of the coalition supporting the government), and two representatives from the national bar association elected by the bar’s governing council. For many years the three justices were thought to have coordinated their positions with respect to individual nominations, which was pejoratively described as “voting as a bloc.” Further, the bar association was traditionally dominated by the same demographic and ideological forces as was the court itself. The result was a system in which a five-person majority could perpetuate the court’s general orientation and, perhaps equally important, veto the appointment of justices who might form the core of a consistent and intellectually strong dissenting group.65

The tension between the government and the Supreme Court’s supporters led to several changes in the nomination committee’s practices. In 2008 a statute increased the number of votes required for appointment from five to seven. This had two effects: the judge-bar association members had to attract votes from the political members for any affirmative appointment, and the judicial members retained the power to veto appointments.66 And in 2009 two court critics were appointed by the legislature, increasing the strength of the “political” group from three to four. This was not enough to push a nomination through without support from either the bar association members or some of the judges, but enough to veto an appointment.67 One effect was the appointment to the court of Alex Stein, an Orthodox legal academic specializing in the uncontroversial fields of torts and medical ethics; conservatives hoped (without much evidence) that he would join the conservative judges already on the court, and liberals hoped (on the same evidence) that he would not.

Discussions of court reform proposals in Israel continued after this change. Characterizing the proposals as threats to judicial independence and constitutional rights is part of the standard vocabulary in those discussions. In 2011, for example, bills that would further tinker with the judicial selection process and allow a conservative jurist to become President of the Court were described as “bills . . . [to] compromise the Supreme Court and the independence of the judges.”68 More recently, the head of the bar association referred to a proposed addition of a “notwithstanding” clause to the Basic Law: Human Dignity and Liberty in this way: “Without an independent and robust judicial system, Israeli democracy and the necessary balance between authorities will suffer a critical blow.”69

The reference to “Israeli democracy” is key here. Canada, the origin of the notwithstanding mechanism, is a well-functioning democracy in which human rights are reasonably well-protected. In other contexts, such as Israel, such a clause—and what elsewhere might seem like minor modifications in judicial selection processes—might pose more substantial threats to democracy. Again, our theme emerges: analyze specific “populist” actions in their socio-political context. That an action is motivated by opposition to, for example, prior court decisions is part of that context—but so, of course, are the merits of the decisions leading to the reform proposals.

3. Poland

After winning a parliamentary majority in 2015, the new Law and Justice (PiS: Pravo i Sprawiedliwošč) populist government in Poland quickly identified the Constitutional Tribunal (Tribunal) as a main “obstacle” to its plans.70 Jaroslav Kaczynski, the party’s leader, observed that “the reforms [of] the constitutional court . . . were needed to ensure there are no legal blocks on government policies aimed at creating a fairer economy.”71 In the early years of the post-communist transition period, the Constitutional Tribunal emerged as a “strong protector of democratic processes and of limits upon legislative and executive powers.”72 The Tribunal’s importance increased as its judgments attracted widespread attention from the legal profession and broader political audiences. Its power to review the constitutionality of statutes challenged the almost absolute supremacy the legislatures previously enjoyed. Because of the distrust of “ordinary” judges, many tainted by their service in the communist regime, constitutional courts became the centerpiece of the protection of the rule of law. But, in a centralized model of judicial review, only constitutional courts had the power of judicial review of legislation. That made the constitutional courts an easy target for populists determined to dismantle the “undemocratic” rule of elite, liberal judges.

The first time the PiS was in power, from 2005 to 2007, the tribunal blocked a number of the government’s plans. In May 2007, the tribunal invalidated several key sections of Poland’s lustration law, the signature piece of legislation of that time, which governed the participation of former communists in government and the civil service.73 Angered by the ruling, then–prime minister Jaroslaw Kaczyñski threatened to charge the judges for having acted “improperly.”

Eight years later, Mr. Kaczynski, PiS’s de facto leader, whose ultimate goal has been described as “a systematic and relentless annihilation of all independent powers which may check the will of the ultimate leader,”74 seized the opportunity and turned the Constitutional Tribunal into an almost harmless judicial body. The government managed with relative ease to render the constitutional court toothless by using ordinary procedures to pack it with loyalists, which after one year resulted in gaining a majority over the Tribunal. As Wojciech Sadurski shows in his study of this transformation, the PiS-appointed judges “effectively paralyzed the Constitutional Tribunal, rendering it unable to subject new laws to effective constitutional scrutiny.”75 Gaining the blessing of powerful court for controversial initiatives required manipulation and intimidation.76

Court-packing was not the only process that PiS used to render the Tribunal subservient to its political will. The second strategy involved a series of legislative proposals clearly aiming at curtailing the Tribunal’s independence. In one year, from 2015 to 2016, the PiS-controlled Parliament adopted six new statutes on the Constitutional Tribunal, transforming it into “a positive aide” to the government.77 One key provision raised the bar for finding unconstitutionality substantially: rulings now have to be approved by a two-thirds majority, making it almost impossible to annul Law and Justice-backed legislation.78 Moreover, the so-called Repair Act on the Constitutional Tribunal, as the new amending law is called, seems to be custom—made to paralyze the Tribunal. Cases will have to wait in the docket for at least six months before they can be decided.

Nevertheless, in March 2016, the Polish Constitutional Tribunal unexpectedly struck back, declaring many of the new provisions to be in violation of the constitution. In a decision that deepened Poland’s constitutional crisis, the Tribunal ruled that the reorganization called for by the new legislation prevented the Tribunal from working “reliably and efficiently.” Shortly afterward, Poland’s Supreme Court (the country’s highest appellate court for non-constitutional matters) passed a resolution stating that the rulings of the Constitutional Tribunal should be respected, despite its stalemate with the government. The government, however, announced that it would ignore the Tribunal’s ruling and refused to publish it in the official Gazette, as required by the constitution.79 An enraged Kaczyñski addressed the Sejm, condemning both high courts for opposing reforms passed by parliament. “[We] will not permit anarchy in Poland,” Kaczyñski declared, “even if it is promoted by the courts.”80

A year later, Poland’s parliament approved the new Supreme Court legislation aimed at curtailing the judiciary, the country’s last bastion of independence. After neutralizing the constitutional courts, the populist governments continued their legal “revolution” with attacks on lower (regular) courts. The Polish government prepared three bills, recently adopted by the Sejm, which aim to control and capture the Supreme Court and the vast majority of other regular courts. By lowering the judicial retirement age (to age of 65), the government first removed most of the presidents of the courts and then replaced them with judges more to his liking.81

We have recounted only a small part of the complex and on-going story about court “reforms” in Poland motivated by hostility to prior judicial rulings and concerns about potential future ones. Even this snippet shows that the Polish story is one about a true assault on judicial independence, badly motivated and covered with at best a fig leaf of legality, if that.

4. Conclusion

Scholarship on populism has taken “reforms” directed at the courts to illustrate the conflict between populism and constitutionalism. We have tried to show that the stories about specific changes motivated by hostility to the courts in place are more complex. Sometimes the challenges posed by populist reforms are ambiguous, sometimes they are clear—and perhaps, though we do not have a clear case study, perhaps sometimes they pose no real challenges to judicial independence. Our theme, though, remains the same: Analyzing the relation between populist reforms and constitutionalism (here, judicial independence) requires close attention to local circumstances rather than broad-brush derivations from general descriptions of both populism and constitutionalism.82

B. Referendums

Legislation by the people themselves may be the cleanest example of barebones populism.83 We consider here what we believe to be the two most prominent concerns about the compatibility of referendums with constitutionalism: (1) that referendums can oversimplify complex policy options in ways that sometimes produce outcomes that are indefensible in principle, incoherent, and inconsistent with what the people would prefer after the kind of deliberation that occurs in representative assemblies;84 and (2) that referendums systematically, though not inevitably, threaten rights of minorities that liberal constitutionalism guarantees.85 The frame of the discussion, though, is that barebones populism leaves substantial room for policy choice through “ordinary” legislation pursuant to ordinary procedural rules. Barebones populism might use referendums more frequently than non-populist constitutionalist systems and, perhaps more importantly, might use referendums in exactly the circumstances in which procedural regularity obstructs the determination of what the people prefer (with the referendum serving as the mechanism for reliably determining that preference).

1. Complexity

The Brexit referendum illustrates many aspects of the first concern. The implications of one of the options—Exit—were unclear because Exit could occur in many ways.86 We can call this a problem of complexity: the people were asked to choose between a simple option and a complex one.87 Even a referendum cast in “yes–no” terms can be complex. Consider for example a referendum on this question: “Should the following complicated tax law be adopted?” Complexity cannot be eliminated by offering the people several options: “Remain,” “Exit on the following terms,” and “Exit on these alternative terms,” or the like. Formulating a complete set of options may be difficult or impossible. Even more, a referendum with more than two options makes the appearance of a Condorcet voting paradox possible, even likely, if (as might well be) the complexity is not characterized by those features of policy choices that make preference rankings single-peaked.

The idea of a voting paradox brings out one key problem with referendums on complex issues. Begin with the observation that policy proposals that are complex in this sense have numerous components. A person might prefer component A to component B only if the overall policy also contains component M. Some such preferences might be nonnegotiable, so to speak. The “only if” is quite strong. Other such preferences might be quite weak. The voter’s view is that having components A and M is desirable, but a policy that contains component A but not M is tolerable if the policy contains a substantial number of other components unrelated to A and M (and similarly for other people and other components).88

Yet, the difficulty posed by complexity might not distinguish referendums strongly enough from ordinary legislative deliberation to count against the at least occasional use of referendums to determine public policy views. A voting paradox based on nonnegotiable demands can occur with respect to ordinary legislation considered by a representative assembly, that is, even within the barebones notion of constitutionalism. Sometimes it is said that a referendum presents people with a choice that cannot be amended or tinkered with to come up with a better option. In contrast, it is said, legislators can negotiate until they have before them a complex proposal that has a chance of being satisfactory to a majority. That contrast is overdrawn. Referendum proposers have an interest in allowing discussion and modifications that increase the proposal’s chance of adoption once submitted. A representative can refuse to vote in favor a proposal that fails to satisfy a nonnegotiable requirement; a voter can vote “No” on any proposal that similarly fails to satisfy her nonnegotiable requirements. Representatives can make judgments that the proposal before them, while not perfect, is on balance better than the status quo; so can voters.

But, one might say, legislators have an opportunity to take successive votes. If a complex proposal is defeated on the floor because it is not on balance acceptable to a majority, representatives can retreat to the committee room and modify the proposal, then present the modification to see if it is acceptable—and they can do so repeatedly.89 Referendums are one-shot events, with no opportunity for a do-over. This is not a necessary characteristic of referendums. In principle the people could be asked to vote repeatedly on variants of rejected proposals. In practice, though, successive referendums on variants are unlikely.90

A clear policy can be a bad one, of course, just as legislation can be bad. The solution to a bad statute is to repeal it. The solution to a referendum that generates bad policy is the same. We can allow the legislature to treat a policy adopted through referendum as it treats any other piece of legislation, subject to immediate revision or even repeal. Or, we can allow the legislature to modify a policy adopted through a referendum only after a prescribed period such as two years. Or, we can allow modifications of referendum-adopted policy only by a second referendum.91

Complex policies, and some simple ones, have other characteristics. They have to be integrated into the existing corpus juris, and they might fit badly or cause unanticipated consequences. A distinctively U.S. example is this: a referendum strictly limiting a legislature’s ability to modify the existing property tax system may lead legislatures to increase sales taxes in ways that have troubling distributional effects, and it almost certainly will cause people to stay in the homes they own longer than is good for them. Again, in principle, there is a simple solution to this problem when it arises. A referendum-adopted policy with these characteristics should impose an obligation on the legislature to adapt the corpus juris to this new feature.92 And, if and when unanticipated consequences appear, the overall policy-making system should be allowed to address those consequences by the mechanisms described in the immediately preceding paragraph.

Suppose we do say that referendums should be allowed only if they offer a choice between two clear policies. Where a complex policy is placed before the public, the alternative should be “No” rather than another complex policy, because “forcing” a choice between two complex policies does not allow a voter to express a preference for the status quo or for another complex policy.

We might be concerned that clarity as a solution to the problem of complexity would create a different problem. In politics clear and accurate policy descriptions might be misleading. This might be particularly true of complex policies presented to the public as a list of clear components. Ordinary people might focus on one or two of the components on the list and not appreciate how those components might interact with other components in ways that alleviate (or exacerbate) the voters’ concerns. Even more, political leaders might make one or two components the focus of their campaigns for or against the referendum, again with misleading effect.

One can imagine institutional responses to concern about misleading clarity. In the United States presumptively disinterested officials are sometimes charged with developing neutral and accurate descriptions of ballot propositions that are distributed to the public in advance (and that sometimes appear on the ballot as well).93 More significant, though, the concern about misleading clarity rests on assumptions about voter incompetence. And barebones populism rests on the contrary assumption, that ordinary people are at least as competent as the representatives they elect in making political decisions. Perhaps critics of referendums could develop more precise accounts of specific forms of voter competence that would be consistent with the assumptions of popular constitutionalism that would allow some but not all referendums on complex policy questions.94 Such accounts would of course have to explain why representatives would not adopt the same sort of distorting clarity in their deliberations that critics cite in opposing referendums on clear questions over which popular discussion might be distorted.

Should simplicity be another criterion for referendums? Consider a referendum on the question, “Should the legislature guarantee a minimum income of at least X—adjusted for inflation—to every person residing in the nation?” This proposal is clear.95 It is not simple, though. It implicates complicated policy questions: How much less (if at all) will people work if guaranteed a minimum income? What will the effects on economic growth be? It also implicates moral questions: What duties do we have to non-citizen residents, whether long-term or otherwise? Barebones populism rests on the not-obviously incorrect judgment that ordinary people are not systematically worse than their representatives in assessing these policy and moral questions.96

The concerns about relative voter competence arise in connection with the policy dimension of this and similar proposals. The moral dimension is sometimes thought to raise different concerns. The problem is not that some moral questions are complicated. Rather, the problem is something akin to self-interest: Voters who asked about the rights of non-citizens are, it is suggested, likely to undervalue those rights relative to their own rights or, more important, their own interests.

2. Referendums on Rights

This concern is brought home most clearly in suggestions that it is inappropriate to subject questions about individual rights to referendums.97 John G. Matsusaka’s conclusion from his review of referendums in the United States is that “[i]nitiatives do pose a threat to minority rights, but . . . the threat is not immense.”98 The most common example from recent history is the Swiss referendum approving a limitation on the construction of minarets. Yet, we should keep in mind the equally recent Irish referendums on marriage equality and abortion (and the Australian quasi-referendum on marriage equality) in thinking about the “no referendums on individual rights” proposition.

These examples suggest that we could benefit from a more differentiated analysis. The distinction between rights and specifications can be helpful here. First, the government policies associated with specifications typically serve non-trivial public interests in a not entirely unreasonable way. Consider restrictions on tobacco advertising: In the language that prevails in comparative constitutional discourse, such restrictions impair the advertisers’ free speech interests in the service of important public health goals. One might reasonably believe that specifying the content of a right of free expression so as to allow such restrictions is reasonable—though of course, one could reasonably take the converse view.

In these and similar cases, we can see how reasonable people could disagree about whether the government policy does indeed violate the right. It is not clear that ordinary people are incompetent or likely to be biased in evaluating whether a referendum threatens rights in a case of specification. Or, more narrowly, perhaps we can make progress in figuring out the difference between the Swiss minaret referendum and the Irish referendums by thinking about why ordinary people might have been biased in the first but not the second and third cases.

Second, perhaps unreasonable specifications result at least as much from self-interested decisions by political leaders—from representative government—as from self-interest among the general population. This is clearest with respect to sedition law: political leaders who develop policy are likely to be especially sensitive about criticisms of their policies, perhaps more so than the voters they represent. For that reason, they may be more likely to adopt a sedition law than would the people through a referendum. Similarly, John Hart Ely’s account of the proper bases for constitutional review refers to the fact that the “Ins” are sensitive to challenges from the “Outs.”99 And here, he rather clearly had legislators in mind, not the voters they represent.

This second thought might also lead to a more refined account of the circumstances under which referendums implicating questions of individual rights might be appropriate—roughly, in cases involving unreasonableness. We note one difficulty, though: political leaders might see political advantage in promoting a referendum on a specification even if ordinary people on their own would not put the referendum process in motion. This might suggest some sort of institutional response through the development of some limits on the role political leaders can play in referendum campaigns. What such limits (consistent with ideas about freedom of expression) could be is unclear, though.

3. The Critique Generalized

Drawing on William Scheuerman’s theorization of the “social acceleration” of political time, Ming-Sung Kuo provides a general critique of what he calls “instantaneous democracy,” which might be thought applicable to the populist use of referendums.100 Following an outline provided by Jeremy Waldron, Kuo enumerates ten (“or so”) stages that, he argues, are required for enactments and other forms of law-making such as constitutional amendment and the development of the common law. He links these to the standard Montesquiean tripartite structure of separated powers, though he does not contend that each set of grouped stages must be institutionalized in a U.S.-style separation of powers system.

Kuo argues that these stages are “articulated”—linked temporally, with some time spent at each stage. But, he argues, instantaneous democracy makes it possible to truncate the time spent at each stage. For Kuo, instantaneous democracy consists of a variety of mechanisms by which what he calls “unformed public opinion” can intervene at each stage. By “unformed public opinion,” he appears to mean views of “the people” that are not sufficiently deliberated before their expression.101 He contrasts this with the traditional view of public decision-making, where public opinion is mediated by such institutions as political parties and the mass media before it affects the policy-making stages.102 Instantaneous democracy creates the “risk of merging [the stages] into a single, mixed stage, so to speak.”103

Here are Professor Kuo’s first three stages, all related to initial adoption of a legal instrument: “the people must be able to envisage the desired political action (I), formulate the action plan as a policy in a legislative bill (II), and enact the policy into law through the legislative processes of deliberation and voting (III).”104 Notably, referendums—even badly designed ones—proceed through these stages. Someone—a political party or an NGO, for example—has to come up with an idea to be put forward as a referendum and then come up with a specific proposal that can be placed on the referendum ballot. There will inevitably be discussion—deliberation?—about whether the idea is worth pursuing and about whether the particular version is desirable.

For example, Switzerland held a referendum in 2016 on whether the nation should guarantee a national income. That idea had been circulating in academic circles for years and ultimately gained support from two Swiss NGOs. They circulated a petition that obtained the requisite number of signatures. None of this was “instantaneous,” nor in any contemporary setting could it be. Professor Kuo’s third stage, then, seems to be the place where all the work is done, at least with respect to referendums, and the discussions appear to have been no less substantive and deliberative than legislative discussion would have been. As we have suggested, the relevant question is comparative: is the degree or quality of deliberation better in legislative forums than in referendum campaigns?105 In Switzerland, the proposal as placed on the ballot would have provided a basic income to all Swiss residents. Among the issues discussed during the campaign was how the guaranteed income would be set, and whether it should be guaranteed only to Swiss citizens rather than all residents. As far as we can tell the quality of deliberation was no worse than it would have been in a legislative debate.

Neither a single example nor an accumulation of anecdotes can establish the general proposition that referendum campaigns are as deliberative as legislative debates. But, again as we have noted, today’s populists do not contend that referendums should completely displace legislatures, or that referendums should resolve all contentious issues of public policy.106 So, the relevant question must be refined: with respect to the subset of policy issues that populists believe should be submitted to referendums, is the quality of deliberation worse than in legislative debates on the same issues? We are not clear on how the burden of proof should be allocated on the question: Should defenders of referendums or of legislation, as it actually occurs, have that burden? That, though, seems to us the real question.

C. Creative Populist Institutions Consistent with Constitutionalism

Barebones populism requires mechanisms for reliably determining popular views on questions of public policy. Recently scholars and practitioners of institutional design have explored mechanisms for identifying popular preferences consistent with a popular constitutionalist version of these requirements of modest constitutionalism. These mechanisms are good candidates for inclusion in the set of institutions for implementing popular constitutionalism. We describe a few here and then identify some problems with them.

Deliberative polling. Political scientist James Fishkin developed a technology he calls deliberative polling.107 In ordinary polling, the pollster asks a large number of randomly selected people a series of relatively short questions, sometimes preceded by a tiny bit of information to set the context. A typical question might be, “Do you think President Trump’s policies are helping the nation’s economy, hurting the nation’s economy, or aren’t making much of a difference?” Answering such questions does not take much time.

Deliberative polling brings together a smaller group of randomly selected people for a longer period. A typical poll covers only a handful of issues, sometimes even just one issue. Deliberative pollsters give the respondents a packet of materials developed by experts describing the issues in some detail from a variety of political and policy perspectives. Then the respondents sit down to talk about the issues. Experience with deliberative polling strongly suggests that people who start out disagreeing with each other can hash out their differences and end up generally agreeing on how to deal with the policy questions they’ve been asked to consider.108

Deliberative polling has been used outside the United States to generate proposals on constitutional matters: Korean unification, schooling in Northern Ireland, and whether Australia should become a republic. Perhaps because of the scope of the issues such polls have dealt with, their immediate impact on policy has been relatively small, though the results may have had some modest effect in shaping public debates.109

Participatory budgeting. Participatory budgeting begins with neighborhood assemblies, usually of volunteers (but other modes of choosing members of these assemblies exist). Each assembly discusses the members’ priorities for spending their portion of the city’s budget and can recommend not only priorities but amounts to be spent. The recommendations from the neighborhood assemblies are sent forward to a city-wide citizen assembly, composed similarly. That assembly takes the recommendations and determines priorities and budget allocations for each neighborhood and for the city as a whole. Typically, these last determinations are simply advisory to the city’s governing authorities, although in principle they could be binding, at least if the assemblies also could determine where the revenue to support spending programs would come from.110 The model of participatory budgeting can be extended to regional and even national budgets.

In late 2019, the parliament of the Brussels region in Belgium adopted regulations embedding a combination of deliberative polling and participatory budgeting in its structure.111 The regulations authorize the creation of a “parliamentary committee” consisting of fifteen members of parliament and forty-five randomly selected citizens to develop policy proposals on specified topics.112 The committees are to meet for four days of hearings and deliberations on topics proposed by citizen petitions. The parliamentarians and the citizen-members can generate separate policy proposals, and if so, both are voted upon separately—the citizen proposals in secret, the parliamentary ones in public. Proposals that receive majority support are reported to the parliamentary members, who have six months to produce a report describing what has been done with the recommendations, offering “detailed reasons” for its actions. Among the possibilities, of course, is rejection by the Parliament as a whole.

Drafting a new constitution for Iceland. For about a decade, a “crowd-sourced” constitution has been on Iceland’s political agenda. Outraged at the political elite’s failures, which culminated in a disastrous financial crisis in 2008, Icelanders developed an innovative process for drafting a new constitution.113

The first step was an assembly convened by a nongovernmental organization. The assembly brought together 1,200 people chosen at random from the national census list and 300 representatives of Icelandic companies and other groups to discuss national problems. Ultimately, the assembly recommended adoption of a new constitution. The national legislature then set up elections for a “constitutional assembly.” Anyone could nominate himself or herself to sit in the assembly, but people currently serving as political party officers or holding political office were disqualified from serving. More than 500 people ran for the 25 seats.

The constitutional assembly operated as a standard constitutional convention, except that it was internet-accessible. Everything it did was almost immediately available on the internet, and it accepted suggestions from the public for constitutional provisions—the crowd-sourcing part of its design. Some of these suggestions were of course lunatic, and some bolstered ideas that were already on the agenda, but the assembly took some crowd-sourced suggestions seriously.

The public endorsed the constitution the assembly came up with in a referendum that was technically only advisory to the legislature. The legislature in turn stifled the proposal, partly because Iceland had recovered well from the financial crisis and partly because the legislature’s political parties had opposed rewriting the constitution from the beginning. Elections in 2017 revived the idea of adopting the new constitution because of the new Pirate Party’s electoral success. Though that party was ultimately left out of the coalition government, its advocacy of constitutional reform kept the issue alive.114

All of these techniques have obvious drawbacks.115 Critics have questioned, for example, the neutrality of the expert briefing material presented in deliberative polling116 and the possibility of getting a truly representative group of people to take the time to participate. The Icelandic constitutional process generated a document that, according to some constitutional experts, had some technical flaws. It has not yet been concluded because, by design, it bypassed the political parties whose support was important in moving the project forward. Notably, though, a new party saw political advantage in backing the proposal, and the new party’s success has kept the project alive. No matter what, though, Iceland is an unusual case because the nation’s population is under 350,000, and the process used there might not “scale” in larger jurisdictions. We note, though, that some versions of participatory budgeting have been implemented in cities and provinces with populations much larger than Iceland’s.117

We address in a bit more detail one objection to these techniques. Almost by definition they do not give special weight to those thought to be most knowledgeable about specific matters.118 It might be thought undesirable for the institution that makes binding policy on matters requiring special knowledge to identify and elaborate good policy to lack guarantees of access to such knowledge.119

Populists have several plausible responses to this objection. First, it overestimates the degree to which specialists actually have specialized knowledge and underestimates the degree to which such knowledge is available within a population of ordinary people.120 Second, it underestimates the degree to which the results counseled by specialized knowledge should often be modified in light of concerns that ordinary people can bring to the table at least as effectively as specialists can.121 Third, sometimes domains in which specialized knowledge really is required can be identified in advance and exempted from these mechanisms.122

The technocratic concern is of course basically an objection to populism as such. It does not seem to us to identify a tension between populism and barebones constitutionalism, or even between populism and rather thicker forms of constitutionalism.

D. A Note on Populism and Rights123

The availability of reasonable alternative specifications means that the definition of constitutionalism is parasitic upon choices among controversial accounts of liberalism’s requirements.124 We can of course engage in reasoned discussion of which is the best account of liberalism with respect to various elements such as free expression and equality. We doubt that we gain much by escalating those discussions into the domain of disagreements about what constitutionalism requires.

In light of the availability of reasonable alternative specifications, what do we gain by defining constitutionalism in more-than-barebones terms? We might wonder why an ideal of constitutionalism is needed, rather than an ideal with respect to each of its components. That is, suppose we observe some departure from the ideal version of free expression. That provides a basis for criticizing the system with respect to free expression. But it is not obvious that it provides a basis for criticizing the system on the ground that it falls short of an ideal of constitutionalism. Suppose, for example, that system A fully satisfies a robust definition of constitutionalism with respect to equality, but falls short with respect to free expression, and that system B exhibits the departures in reverse: falling short on equality but fully satisfying free expression. Criticisms based on shortfalls on each dimension make sense; criticism that both systems are defective from the point of view of constitutionalism seems to us more questionable.

One possibility is simple: make “constitutionalism” itself a dimensional idea. We could have strong constitutionalist systems, modest constitutionalist ones, and weak constitutionalist ones. We would place systems in the appropriate categories by making a judgment about where on each component of constitutionalism the system lies (strong on the free expression dimension, weaker on the equality dimension, and the like), assigning weights to the components (free expression getting more weight than equality, or the reverse), and then aggregating those judgments. The important point here is that the terms “strong,” “modest,” and “weak,” are descriptive, not normative. That is, weak constitutionalist systems are not inferior, qua constitutional systems, to stronger ones because each system’s version of each component instantiates a reasonable specification of the component’s content (again, free expression, equality, and the like).

The conclusion here is, again, that we should have a language of constitutionalism capable of treating all systems that incorporate reasonable specifications of each component of liberal constitutionalism as constitutional systems tout court. This diminishes and might even eliminate the supposed tension between generic populism and constitutionalism, replacing it with a more disaggregated analysis focusing on specific populisms.

III. The Argument Applied

We provide here two case studies in which some have argued that populism conflicts with constitutionalism: the Brexit referendum, the possibility of a second Brexit referendum, and the UK Supreme Court’s decision invalidating Boris Johnson’s prorogation of Parliament in 2019. In each we argue that asserting that the case for a conflict between populism and constitutionalism obscures more than it illuminates, and the more granular analysis suggested by our approach is better.125

A. The Brexit Referendum

On Thursday, June 23, 2016, the United Kingdom held a historic referendum on Britain’s continuing membership in the European Union. On a high turnout of 72.2% of the registered voters, 51.9% voted to leave, against 48.1% who voted to remain. The referendum was characterized as “the most significant development in the history of European integration”126 and as “the most significant constitutional event in Britain since the Restoration in 1660.”127

As Kenneth Armstrong explains, referendums “are not quite the constitutional novelty that they once were in the UK.” 128 In the last four decades, there were three UK-wide referendums: two on independence of Scotland (1979 and 2014) and the Brexit referendum in 2016. Stephen Tierney identifies several important reasons for this trend both in the United Kingdom and around the world.129 One of them is “cognitive mobilisation,” “the increasing sophistication of contemporary electorates through better education and access to information”;130 this leads to stronger popular pressure for a greater say in governmental decision‐making. Another is increasing voter dissatisfaction with conventional representative politics. Barebones populists need not see these developments as troublesome.

With the referendum no longer a constitutional anomaly, the Political Parties, Elections, and Referendums Act was passed in 2000 to provide basic legal rules regulating the conduct of future referendums. One of the key novelties of this act was the establishment of an Electoral Commission with oversight functions, including giving advice on referendum questions.131 The Commission tests questions to determine their intelligibility and whether the question’s phrasing does not frame the matter in a way conducing voters to choose one side or the other.

In our view, the Brexit referendum failed to satisfy a central element of the barebones definition of populism—that the views of a current majority of citizens be reliably determined. The reason is that, though referendums are in principle one mechanism for obtaining a reliable determination, to do so they must avoid oversimplification of complex policy options. The Brexit referendum failed in this regard. More precisely, the reason for the failure lies not in the complexity of the “leave or stay” choice itself, but rather lay in posing the choice badly. Perhaps the question of UK membership in the European Union can be decided by the use of referendum. We agree with Richard Ekins and Graham Gee that “[a] convincing case can be made in representative democracies for occasional use of ‘constitutional referendums’ as a tool for resolving vital questions about the long-term identity of the state, such as the UK’s membership of the EU.”132 The devil, though, is in the details.

In May 2015, the European Referendum Bill was introduced to the House of Commons. The bill proposed a yes/no referendum question: “Should the United Kingdom remain a member of the European Union?” The Electoral Commission determined that the proposed question was misleading because it presupposed that voters knew that the United Kingdom was already an EU member state. The Commission recommended a new formulation, which then became the accepted version in the final bill. The referendum question therefore was: “Should the United Kingdom remain a member of the European Union or leave the European Union?”133

Framing the referendum question in such a simplistic and binary way failed to provide any guidance on what kind of a future relationship with the European Union the United Kingdom had in mind for itself. As we noted earlier, the implications of the “leave” option were unclear because Brexit could occur in many ways. For example, four such possibilities had been made clear by the European Union Committee of the House of Lords in a report entitled “Brexit: The Options for Trade.”134 The report listed four options: EEA (European Economic Area) membership or the “Norway deal”; an agreement to remain in the customs union, but not in the single market (the “Turkey deal”); an ad hoc trade agreement with the EU outside the single market (the “Canada deal”); and, finally, the hard Brexit—trade on the basis of WTO rules outside of the single market. Only the last option (“hard Brexit”) is more or less straightforward because it does not require any negotiations with the European Union. As Pavlos Elefteriadis correctly observes, “given the referendum question, voting ‘Leave’ was not a vote for choosing any particular of the four available options.”135 The referendum rejected the “Remain” option, but left all other future options indeterminate. As a result, it was not clear if the Leave supporters were voting for a “hard Brexit” as the current British Prime minister claims, or for one of many “soft Brexit” options, each entailing different policy options with serious economic and political implications for the future UK-EU relationship. As Liubomir Topaloff asks, “Would voters have opted for Leave had they known that their vote would trigger a ‘hard exit’ option that would end the free movement of capital, goods, and services, along with that of people and would ultimately increase the cost to U.K. taxpayers?”136

The referendum provided a mandate for the ultimate goal—leaving the EU—but not for how that would be achieved. Kevin O’Rourke argues that the electoral logic of the referendum “seemed to imply that the government should pursue what soon became known as a ‘soft Brexit,’ that is to say a Brexit that involved the United Kingdom remaining inside the EU’s Single Market, or a customs union with the EU, or both.”137 However, quite soon a number of other things were said to be mandated by the results of the referendum. When Theresa May became Prime Minister, she imposed her “red lines” which were understood to follow from the referendum result: the result was taken to mean that the UK would take control of its money, laws, and borders. These “red lines” meant that the UK could not be a member of the single market or the customs union and entailed ending the jurisdiction of the Court of Justice of the European Union.138

The Brexit referendum led to a protracted period of political events that eventually ended the Brexit drama with the formal exit of the United Kingdom from the European Union on January 31, 2020. However, as it became clear after Boris Johnson became a new Prime Minister in July 2019, the process of creative “reinterpretation” of the Brexit referendum is likely to continue in the future. After declaring that his government intends to “get Brexit done,” it became clear that his understanding of the Brexit referendum favors the “hard Brexit” option. And that indeed is what happened.

B. Miller/Cherry (No. 2): Populism vs Judicial Supremacy?

In its “historic” judgment in Miller/Cherry (No. 2),139 the UK Supreme Court unanimously held that the prorogation140 of Parliament for a period of five weeks was unlawful, void, and without legal effect. The case concerned whether the advice given by Prime Minister Boris Johnson to Queen Elizabeth II that Parliament should be prorogued for five weeks during the closing stages of the Brexit process was lawful. As the Supreme Court explained in the key passage of its judgment:

[A] decision to prorogue Parliament (or to advise the monarch to prorogue Parliament) will be unlawful if the prorogation has the effect of frustrating or preventing, without reasonable justification, the ability of Parliament to carry out its constitutional functions as a legislature and as the body responsible for the supervision of the executive. In such a situation, the court will intervene if the effect is sufficiently serious to justify such an exceptional course.141

The decision was celebrated by some as “the most significant judicial statement on the constitution in over 200 years,” to be “discussed centuries from now,”142 and criticized, by others, as “a historic mistake”143 to be reversed by the next Parliament.

Prorogation took effect at a delicate time for the UK Brexit political saga. While Johnson rejected claims that his decision was designed to block MPs from considering ways to thwart his Brexit plans after he was accused of mounting a “coup” against parliament, it was quite clear from the outset that that was Johnson’s covert aim behind the prorogation, officially justified by Johnson as the move that would allow him to “bring forward an ambitious new legislative programme for MPs’ approval.” For prorogation to last more than a month is unprecedented in recent times: Since the 1980s prorogation has typically lasted less than a week. The length of the prorogation would clearly have the effect of narrowing rebel MPs’ options—they would have several weeks fewer in parliament to pass any anti-no-deal legislation.

Taking prorogation to be an example of a populist action,144 we think that Miller/Cherry poses two questions: (1) Was it appropriate for the Supreme Court to rule on the merits (or should the problem have been left to political constitutionalism)? (2) Was the Supreme Court correct on the merits?

The court spent most time asking whether prorogation is reviewable by the courts. Under British constitutional law, the executive branch of government enjoys a number of prerogative powers, such as declaring war and making treaties, which are sometimes, but not always,145 exempted from judicial review. Many considered prorogation to be among the political matters exempted from judicial scrutiny. The court, on the other hand, made it quite clear that the fact that a question before it “is political in tone or context”146 cannot render the matter non-justiciable.147 As Mark Elliott explains, the crucial issue for the court was “whether the scope of that power had been exceeded” and whether “the power had been used for an improper purpose—such as avoiding accountability to Parliament—then this would render the issue justiciable.”148

The court then explained the standard that determines the limits of the prerogative power. The court invoked two fundamental constitutional principles, parliamentary sovereignty and parliamentary accountability, to justify its ruling. The first principle limits the executive “to have legally unfettered authority to prorogue Parliament.” As Mark Elliott explains:

This does not mean that the Court could or should rule, at the level of detail, on what is and is not an acceptable period of prorogation. What it does mean, however, is that it would be incompatible with parliamentary sovereignty for the executive to have legally unfettered authority to prorogue Parliament.149

The second principle of parliamentary accountability was, according to the court, “no less fundamental to our constitution than Parliamentary sovereignty.”150 Citing Lord Bingham, the court gave the following definition to this principle: “the conduct of government by a Prime Minister and Cabinet collectively responsible and accountable to Parliament lies at the heart of Westminster democracy.”151 The principle means that:

Ministers are accountable to Parliament through such mechanisms as their duty to answer Parliamentary questions and to appear before Parliamentary committees, and through Parliamentary scrutiny of the delegated legislation which ministers make. By these means, the policies of the executive are subjected to consideration by the representatives of the electorate, the executive is required to report, explain and defend its actions, and citizens are protected from the arbitrary exercise of executive power.152

Finally, applying the principle to the case, the court concluded:

That principle is not placed in jeopardy if Parliament stands prorogued for the short period which is customary, and as we have explained, Parliament does not in any event expect to be in permanent session. But the longer that Parliament stands prorogued, the greater the risk that responsible government may be replaced by unaccountable government: the antithesis of the democratic model.153

For some, the court’s decision signals “the dissolution of the old political constitution.”154 John Finnis goes even further and argues that “the Judgement itself undercuts the genuine sovereignty of Parliament by evading a statutory prohibition—art. 9 of the Bill of Rights 1689—on judicial questioning of proceedings in Parliament.”155 The court dismissed that argument, saying, “The prorogation itself takes place in the House of Lords and in the presence of Members of both Houses. But it cannot sensibly be described as a ‘proceeding in Parliament.’ It is not a decision of either House of Parliament. Quite the contrary: it is something which is imposed upon them from outside. It is not something upon which the Members of Parliament can speak or vote.”156

We agree with Elliott’s argument that “the case amounts to a significant restatement of a range of key matters, but cannot justifiably be criticized as having cast aside established principle or as an instance of improper judicial overreach.”157 At the same time, as Richard Bellamy, a prominent proponent of political constitutionalism, argues, “there is ‘nothing in the substance of the judgment with which a political constitutionalist could disagree.’”158 The prorogation was undoubtedly an act of constitutional hardball, departing from prior practices but arguably within the scope of the prerogative power as previously understood. As we have shown, some scholars believe that the action was within constitutional bounds and that the UK Supreme Court was mistaken. Others, including one of us, are inclined to think that the prorogation was an abuse of power.

What are we to make of a case where there appear to be plausible arguments supporting both sides when some seemingly detached observers find one or the other side’s argument more plausible? Here too the idea that there can be reasonable alternative specifications of agreed-upon legal principles seems helpful. The UK Supreme Court chose one of several available reasonable specifications of the scope of the prerogative power. Were Parliament to respond by “reining in” the Supreme Court, thereby making it clear that it believes that a different specification was “more” reasonable, it would not thereby undermine constitutionalism in our barebones definition. More generally, the populist-favoring positions—that the question should be left to political constitutionalism, and that the prorogation was constitutionally permissible—fall within the range of reasonable specifications of the content of British constitutionalism.

Conclusion

There is a tendency in current constitutional thinking to reduce populism to a single set of universal elements. These theories juxtapose populism with constitutionalism and argue that populism is by definition antithetical to constitutionalism. As we saw in Part II, this view defines populism in a way that makes populism inconsistent with the very substance of constitutional (liberal) democracy. It attacks the core elements of constitutional democracy, such as independent courts, free media, civil rights, and fair electoral rules, and so pushes democracies into some form of non-democratic and authoritarian order.

We have argued that such an approach is both historically inaccurate and normatively flawed. Some forms of populism, exemplified by the New Deal in the United States, did not degenerate into authoritarianism and, in that case, actually helped American democracy to survive the Great Depression of the 1930s. If the combination between populism and constitutionalism “sounds odd especially to a European ear,”159 populist constitutionalism has a strong resonance among many prominent American constitutional scholars. Looking at the current populist map, we can find examples of similar democratic populists, who seek to protect and defend democracy by making it more responsive, equitable and inclusive. We have argued that it is wrong to argue that there is something intrinsic to populism that makes it incompatible with constitutionalism.160

Rather, we have argued, populism is Janus-faced. It does not take a single form, but a variety of different forms, each with different political consequences. Populism always co-exists with a variety of different host ideologies, which significantly determine how populism affects democracy. As more recent empirical studies of effects of populism on constitutional democracy show, the picture is mixed: populism has both negative and positive consequences for democracy. While it is clear that certain instances of authoritarian nationalist populism lead to democratic backsliding and breakdown, at other times democratic populism can foster democratization. As a result, “despite the fact that there are good reasons for worrying about the rise of populism, scholars are probably putting too much emphasis on the downsides and thus not considering potential positive effects of populist forces.”161 The dominant approach fails to analyze the impact of host ideologies on the electoral appeal of various populist forces. Once we couple populist discourse with (host) ideology, we see a much more complicated pattern of interrelationship between populism and constitutional democracy: Populism comes in different versions, with different effects on constitutionalism and the rule of law.

We must therefore distinguish among forms of populisms: agrarian, socio-economic, xenophobic, reactionary, authoritarian and progressive populism, not all of which, of course, we have attempted to describe in this Essay. While some forms contradict the key principles of modern democratic constitutionalism, others seek to resuscitate the same principles from the grip of the unaccountable “moneyed elites.” As described by James Miller, in Hannah Arendt’s view, “these episodes of collective self-assertion are invariably fleeting and stand in tension with the need for a more stable constitution of collective freedom, embodied in the rule of law, and representative institutions”; for her they represent “a constitutive feature of the modern democratic project.”162 To label them “populist” in a pejorative sense is to misunderstand the inherent instability of the democratic project. As James Miller argues, populist “outbursts are essential to the continued vitality, and viability, of modern democracy—even as (and precisely because) they challenge the status quo, destructive though that challenge may be.”163 A specific instance of populism might be incompatible with a widely accepted ideal of constitutionalism. Another instance of populism might be not only compatible with that ideal but, as Miller suggests, an important or even essential support for it. To reiterate: context matters.


* William Nelson Cromwell Professor of Law Emeritus, Harvard Law School. Professor of Law, University of Sheffield Department of Law. The ideas presented here are developed in more detail in Mark Tushnet & Bojan Bugarič, Power to the People: Constitutionalism in the Age of Populism (forthcoming 2021)