Patent Law’s Externality Asymmetry

Technologies such as social media, autonomous vehicles, and “big data” analytics generate enormous benefits for society, but they also create substantial harms. Many of these effects take the form of externalities—external benefits and harms that a decisionmaker (such as an inventor) imposes on third parties without charge or compensation. Considering negative externalities, for example, social media networks spread misinformation throughout the electorate, autonomous vehicles threaten the jobs of millions of professional drivers, and predictive policing based on big data can lead to unreasonable searches and seizures. Externalities can cause inefficient resource allocation, and the classic remedy is to “internalize” externalities by ensuring that decisionmakers consider the external benefits and costs of their actions. Patents, which confer exclusive rights on new inventions, enable inventors to internalize a share of the positive externalities from technology, thus shoring up incentives to invent. However, inventions also produce harms, and how patents treat negative externalities from new technologies has been largely overlooked. This Article is the first to extensively examine this issue. It argues that while patents internalize positive externalities associated with innovation, they do surprisingly little to internalize negative externalities. This Article refers to this underappreciated dynamic as patent law’s externality asymmetry.

Patent law’s externality asymmetry is particularly striking when comparing patents to physical property rights. Foundational economic theory holds that property rights (including patents) emerge to internalize externalities. However, physical property rights internalize negative externalities in several ways that are inapplicable to patents. Patents do not internalize negative externalities associated with the tragedy of the commons, and they encourage patentees to exploit their technologies rapidly rather than judiciously consider their third-party harms. Due to high transaction costs, patents do not facilitate efficiency-maximizing negotiations between patentees and individuals harmed by their inventions. Finally, patents create no duties for inventors to mitigate harms from their patented technologies. Patents, in other words, allow inventors to capture a meaningful share of the upside of their inventions while largely insulating them from the downside. Turning to normative considerations, this Article argues that patent law’s externality asymmetry is highly problematic because it undermines efficiency, distributive equity, and fairness. It proposes modest reforms to patent law and greater integration of patent and nonpatent regulatory mechanisms to internalize negative externalities from technological innovations.

 

I am not a Luddite. I am suspicious of technology. I am perfectly aware of its benefits, but I also try to pay attention to some of the negative effects.

—Neil Postman

 

All problems of externalities are closely analogous to those which arise in the land ownership example. The relevant variables are identical.

—Harold Demsetz, Toward a Theory of Property Rights

Introduction: The Promise and Perils of Innovation

Humanity’s relationship with technology will define the twenty-first century.1 Technological innovations permeate the most important and intimate areas of life, shaping how we maintain our health, obtain critical information, and connect with loved ones. Technology has advanced to dizzying heights, from 5G wireless networks transmitting data at unprecedented speeds to novel mRNA vaccines developed to combat the coronavirus pandemic.2 The value of technology is so great that the Constitution authorizes a patent system to confer exclusive rights on new inventions, thus promoting technological progress.3 However, alongside significant promise, technologies—including patented technologies—present many perils. Facebook’s patented content-filtering system provides “curated” information to users that reinforces their ideological views, thus exacerbating political polarization throughout the electorate.4 Autonomous vehicles based on patented technology threaten the jobs of millions of professional drivers.5 Patented predictive policing systems based on “big data” can lead to unconstitutional searches and seizures.6

Put differently, patented technologies can generate significant negative externalities. Externalities are benefits or costs imposed on third parties that are external to a decisionmaker. Externalities may be positive, as when an individual gets vaccinated and thereby reduces disease transmission for everyone else.7 Conversely, they may be negative, as when a factory belches pollution that harms nearby residents. Economists warn that significant externalities are problematic because they can lead to inefficient resource allocation. For instance, if a factory does not bear the cost of polluting others, it will operate at a higher capacity than is socially optimal. The classic remedy for externalities is to “internalize” them, which refers to all public or private measures for ensuring that decisionmakers consider external benefits or costs in making some decision. One way of doing so is to hold producers of positive and negative externalities accountable for the benefits and costs, respectively, that they impose on others.

Externalities play a central role in patent law. Commentators have long explored the positive8 and negative9 externalities of subjecting technologies to exclusive rights via the patent system. On a more foundational level, the economics and IP literature has long recognized that technology itself produces positive externalities, also known as spillovers,10 and concern over excessive spillovers provides a foundational justification for the patent system. Consider a regime without patents in which everyone could freely copy the inventions of others. If most of the value of inventions “spilled over” to free riders in the form of positive externalities, inventors would have little incentive to invent new technologies. Patents, which confer twenty years of exclusive rights on technologies, allow inventors to internalize a meaningful share of positive externalities, thus shoring up incentives to invent.

Technology, however, creates substantial costs as well as benefits. The economics and IP literature has largely overlooked—with a few exceptions—the potential for patented technologies to produce significant negative externalities.11 This Article fills this gap. It represents the first extended examination of negative externalities arising from technology and the role of patents in allowing such externalities to persist. Technologies—including patented technologies—generate significant uncompensated harms for third parties. In light of these harms, a natural question arises: What role do patents play in internalizing these negative externalities?

This Article argues that patent law exhibits a striking and overlooked asymmetry: while patents do much to internalize positive innovation externalities, they do very little to internalize negative innovation externalities. This Article refers to this underappreciated dynamic as patent law’s externality asymmetry. As noted, patents exist for the core purpose of internalizing positive externalities. However, patents do almost nothing to internalize negative externalities. On rare occasions, the patent system has denied patents on “immoral” inventions (which may generate significant negative externalities), and a proliferation of patents can in theory slow progress in potentially harmful fields.12 In practice, however, patents allow inventors of social media, automation, and big data technologies to profit from their inventions while doing nothing to internalize these technologies’ external costs. Notably, the patent system is massively subsidizing the invention of technologies that impose uncompensated harms on others.

Patent law’s externality asymmetry is even more striking when situating patents within foundational property theory. This Article gains insights into patent law’s governance of cutting-edge technologies by exploring conceptual parallels with a classic legal regime: property rights in land. Harold Demsetz’s canonical economic analysis argues that property rights arise precisely to internalize positive and negative externalities (when the benefits of internalization outweigh the costs).13 Property rights internalize externalities in at least three ways, although Demsetz focused on the first two. First, property rights mitigate overconsumption associated with the tragedy of the commons and encourage conservation and judicious use of resources. Second, property rights lower transaction costs between landowners and people affected by their activities. By doing so, they facilitate voluntary negotiations that can lead to more efficient resource allocation. Third, property rights establish not only rights to exclude, but also duties to not unreasonably interfere with the property of others. This duty is evident in the doctrine of nuisance, which forces polluters and other offenders to internalize the costs that their actions impose on others. By their structure and design, physical property rights play an important role in internalizing negative externalities. Notably, Demsetz generalized beyond land to argue that property rights serve this function in numerous contexts, including the realm of intellectual property.14

Contrary to this received wisdom, however, patents do little to internalize negative externalities. Many mechanisms by which physical property rights internalize negative externalities do not apply, or do not apply to nearly the same extent, to patents. First, patents do not internalize negative externalities associated with the tragedy of the commons because this tragedy does not apply to the nonrival technical information at the heart of inventions. Such technical information cannot be overconsumed, and so the tragedy of the commons is inapposite. More importantly, rather than encouraging patentees to conserve protected assets, the time-limited nature of patents encourages them to exploit technologies rapidly. Such rapid exploitation is not conducive to patentees engaging in unhurried consideration and mitigation of externalities. Second, patents do not realistically facilitate efficiency-maximizing transactions between technology owners and individuals harmed by their technologies. Although patents lower some transaction costs, private negotiations remain prohibitively costly due to the large number of parties involved and the availability of technological substitutes for any given patented invention. Third, unlike property rights, patents create no duties for resource owners to limit harms imposed on external parties. Nobody has a right to be free from the effects of a patented invention. In sum, patents are a one-way ratchet that allows patentees to internalize positive externalities from technological innovation but does very little to internalize associated negative externalities.

These theoretical insights have significant practical payoff. Turning to normative analysis, this Article argues that patent law’s externality asymmetry contributes to a host of social ills. Most prominently, it undermines efficiency. Reflecting the enduring influence of law and economics, the objective of efficiently allocating resources for innovation has dominated normative discourse on the patent system. However, by not providing effective mechanisms for internalizing negative externalities, patents likely overincentivize innovation, incentivize the wrong mix of innovations, and provide suboptimal incentives for technological design. While scholars have critiqued the patent system on several grounds other than efficiency, even within the dominant idiom of efficiency, it falls short. Looking beyond efficiency, patent law’s externality asymmetry causes other harms as well by undermining distributive equity and fairness.

Turning to policy implications, this Article argues that there is little reason to think that the patent system achieves a socially optimal allocation of resources for innovation. A natural question then arises: What role, if any, should the patent system play in internalizing the negative externalities of patented inventions? Perhaps surprisingly, this Article argues that the patent system as presently constituted can only play a limited role. The inability of patent law to regulate specific uses of technology, as well as difficulties of timing and institutional competence, suggests a narrow role for the patent system in internalizing negative innovation externalities. To ameliorate these deficits, this Article proposes a requirement that would compel patentees to disclose the potentially harmful effects of certain technologies as a condition of obtaining a patent. However, this is a deliberately modest proposal, and this Article’s broader prescription is to call for greater integration of patent and nonpatent mechanisms—such as environmental law, food and drug regulation, tort liability, and tax law—within a holistic framework for internalizing negative externalities from technological innovation. This Article argues that these “restrictive” mechanisms—which seem at odds with patent law’s interest in promoting technological progress—are actually essential to achieving the patent system’s objective of innovative efficiency. Furthermore, this Article argues for expanding the role of the patent system in generating valuable private information to inform regulatory responses to novel technologies. Turning to broader implications, this Article urges greater technological realism in innovation law and policy, and it challenges the fundamental association of property rights and internalizing externalities within economic theory.

The stakes of addressing the negative externalities of innovation are enormous. Undergirding the seemingly abstract concept of externalities are real harms caused by patented inventions. Technologies that the patent system actively subsidizes are degrading political discourse, eliminating jobs, and likely contributing to constitutional violations. Patents and market-based systems of technological development enjoy a presumption of efficiency in the allocation of resources for innovation. However, markets are unlikely to allocate resources efficiently if they ignore wide swaths of external costs. This Article highlights the underappreciated reality that patented technologies generate uncompensated third-party harms; greater attention to externalities (both positive and negative) will lead to more enlightened innovation policy and more efficient resource allocation.

This Article proceeds in five Parts. Part I introduces the concept of externalities. It briefly reviews the widely recognized view that technologies generate significant positive externalities. It then examines the less appreciated ways that technologies—including patented technologies—also generate significant negative externalities. It illustrates this phenomenon through case studies of three patented technologies: social media content filters, autonomous vehicles, and predictive policing based on big data. Part II advances the novel argument that patent law asymmetrically internalizes positive but not negative externalities. Patents allow inventors to internalize external benefits from their inventions, thus shoring up incentives to invent. However, patents do very little to internalize the negative externalities of those inventions. Part III delves deeper into patent law’s externality asymmetry by comparing patents to physical property rights. Drawing on foundational economic theory, it shows how physical property rights internalize externalities in numerous ways that do not apply to patents. Part IV analyzes the normative implications of patent law’s externality asymmetry. It argues that by internalizing positive but not negative externalities, patent law undermines efficiency, distributive equity, and fairness. Part V suggests patent reforms to compel inventors to consider the social implications of their inventions and calls for greater integration of patent and nonpatent mechanisms to internalize negative externalities. Furthermore, it explores the broader implications of this Article for technology policy and economic theory.

I. Innovation Externalities

A. Externalities: An Introduction

While the precise definition of an externality is contested,15 in general it refers to a benefit or cost that an actor imposes on external parties for which there is no charge or compensation. As such, the actor typically does not account for externalities when taking some action.16 Externalities may be positive, often referred to as spillovers. A familiar example is vaccination, which helps the person receiving the shot but also reduces disease transmission for the community at large. Externalities can also be negative. A familiar example from every property casebook is the factory belching pollution that harms nearby residents. Externalities (both positive and negative) are ubiquitous and pervade everyday life.

This Article speaks of technologies as “creating” externalities, particularly negative externalities, and it is helpful to clarify a few matters of terminology. First, it is useful to address the thorny issue of causality. Economist Ronald Coase famously argued that harm is reciprocal and that in any case involving a negative externality between two parties, both parties are but-for causes of the externality.17 Applying this insight to the classic example of pollution, both the factory and the residents harmed by pollution are but-for “causes” of the negative externality; remove either party (or both), and there would be no externality. Similarly, in the technological sphere, if Facebook’s filter bubble degrades the political discourse of citizens, both Facebook and the citizens themselves are but-for causes of this negative externality. Following linguistic and social convention, this Article will speak of active parties (such as technology developers) as imposing externalities on passive parties (such as technology users and society at large), while acknowledging that both are, technically, but-for causes of the externality. Within this framework, Facebook creates an externality for users and society at large when it develops a technology that degrades political discourse.

Second, it is helpful to clarify this Article’s use of “negative” and “positive” externalities. Some commentators note that any situation involving a negative externality could be described in terms of a positive externality (and vice versa).18 Such characterizations depend on the selection of a baseline that is ultimately arbitrary.19 For instance, the “problem” of Facebook’s filter bubble could be understood as either the presence of a negative externality from using a harmful technology or the absence of a positive externality from not using it.20

However, for two reasons, this Article suggests that characterizing a technology’s harms to others as a negative externality is appropriate and does not detract from its overall analysis. First, as has been widely recognized, “normalcy” and reasonable expectations provide, in many instances, a solid guide for characterizing a situation as involving positive or negative externalities.21 While formalistically possible, it strains credulity to characterize a technology developer’s external harm as the absence of internalizing the positive externality of not inventing a technology.22 This Article adopts a “normal” baseline in which the default condition is nonaction and noninteraction.23 Thus, the baseline will be quiet, no pollution, and no innovation. Relative to this baseline, factory owners create negative externalities for neighbors, vaccine recipients create positive externalities for the population at large, and innovators create both positive and negative externalities for others relative to a world in which their innovations do not exist.

Additionally, and more importantly, even if the selection of a baseline is ultimately arbitrary (in other words, there is no a priori, external measure of the “proper” baseline), once a baseline is selected, the concepts of positive and negative externalities in any given situation have internal meaning relative to that baseline. Here, patent law’s asymmetric treatment of externalities on opposite sides of the baseline remains meaningful regardless of what baseline is picked.24 One could say (as this Article does) that patents allow inventors to internalize the positive externalities of their inventions but not the negative externalities of those inventions. Or one could say that patents allow inventors to internalize the negative externalities of not inventing but not the positive externalities of not inventing. Either way, the relative relationships remain intact, and patent law’s asymmetric treatment of positive and negative externalities remains consistent.

Third, economists further distinguish between so-called technological and pecuniary externalities. “Technological” or “real” externalities refer to interparty effects transmitted outside of the market.25 Technological externalities change the production function of a firm (or the utility function of a consumer) so that more or fewer inputs are required to produce an additional unit of output. For example, a factory creates a negative technological externality when it belches pollution next to a restaurant and consequently decreases the productivity of the restaurant workers and the ability of customers to enjoy their meals. Technological externalities are problematic because they drive a wedge between private and social value and can lead to inefficient resource allocation.26 In our example, the private returns of the factory will not equal its social returns because the private returns do not account for the negative externalities imposed on the restaurant and its customers (as well as any other negative externalities). It may be socially efficient for the factory to reduce its operations or even shut down, but the factory is unlikely to do so if it is not accountable for these third-party costs. In general, in markets where actors ignore externalities, production of a good or service that generates negative technological externalities will be too high. Conversely, production of any good or service that generates positive technological externalities will be too low.

Unlike technological externalities, pecuniary externalities work directly through the market.27 Consider a change to our restaurant example: imagine that rather than operating next to a factory, a competing restaurant moves in next door. This new restaurant imposes a negative externality on the original restaurant, which now faces greater competition. However, this is a pecuniary externality rather than a technological externality because it operates directly through the market; competition from the new restaurant decreases the prices the original restaurant can charge for meals and increases wages that it must pay to workers.28 Compared to technological externalities, the welfare effects of pecuniary externalities are more contested. Most economists ignore pecuniary externalities on the theory that they simply result in wealth transfers rather than a wedge between private returns and social returns.29 On this view, pecuniary externalities do not result in resource misallocation.30 Other economists, however, point out that pecuniary externalities can depress overall welfare if markets are not competitive or transactions do not occur.31 Additionally, pecuniary externalities exacerbate distributive inequities,32 which are problematic in their own right and may also impair welfare.33

This Article focuses primarily on technological externalities that result from innovation, though it will at times refer to pecuniary externalities. To minimize confusion, this Article will use the term “innovation externalities” to refer generally to externalities arising from technological innovations in order to differentiate them from the more specific economic concept of “technological externalities.” When appropriate, it will distinguish within innovation externalities between technological and pecuniary externalities.

The classic remedy for problematic externalities is to “internalize” them, which refers to any public or private measures undertaken to ensure that decisionmakers consider unpaid benefits or costs in making some decision. A principal way of doing so is to allow (or force) decisionmakers to bear a greater share of the benefits and costs they create for external parties. In so doing, internalization allows private resource allocation to better reflect social costs and benefits.34 Thus, for example, governments use lotteries and other incentives to subsidize individuals’ decisions to get vaccinated (which has positive externalities) and impose taxes on pollution (which creates negative externalities).

It is important to note that for several reasons, it is neither desirable nor feasible to internalize all externalities.35 For example, a beneficial activity may generate enough private gain for a decisionmaker that she is indifferent to the positive externalities that spill over to others. In these cases, internalizing externalities would lead to social losses that are not offset by private gains. Take, for instance, a gardener who cultivates a beautiful garden that his neighbors enjoy.36 It would make little sense to force the neighbors to compensate him (thus internalizing these positive externalities) given that the gardener already derives sufficient benefit to motivate his gardening. From the perspective of optimizing resource allocation, these positive externalities may simply be “irrelevant.”37 Similarly, internalizing all negative externalities is also not warranted. In a bustling, modern society, people will sometimes bump into each other, talk too loudly at restaurants, and wear overly pungent perfume. The administrative (and other) costs of internalizing every negative externality outweigh the benefits.

More fundamentally, some externalities do not warrant internalization because they are necessarily incidental to activities that increase net social welfare. This point is best illustrated by considering negative externalities. At one end of the spectrum are significant negative externalities that distort resource allocation, such as the factory that creates so much pollution that it represents a net social negative. In such cases, internalizing the externality (leading to the factory closing or reducing output) would be efficient. However, some negative externalities do not warrant internalization because they are necessary byproducts of an activity that is a net social positive. For instance, considering a pecuniary externality, when a new firm enters a market to challenge an established incumbent, we generally tolerate (perhaps even welcome) the negative externality imposed on the incumbent as part and parcel of healthy competition and all its attendant benefits.38 In such cases, internalizing the negative externality by prohibiting competition would be inefficient.

In some contexts, welfare analysis counsels against fully internalizing a negative externality (which would eliminate a related activity that is a net social positive), yet policymakers may seek to partially internalize that externality, perhaps based on considerations of distributive equity or fairness.39 Patent law, which aims to promote technological progress, creates negative externalities by incentivizing novel technologies that render existing ones obsolete.40 For instance, as discussed further below, autonomous vehicles create a negative externality for professional drivers who may lose their jobs.41 Like healthy competition, we generally tolerate the negative externality imposed on legacy technologies by the onward march of technological progress. Assuming (as is likely the case) that the macroscopic benefits of autonomous vehicles outweigh their costs, internalizing this externality by suppressing this technology would decrease overall welfare. However, nonwelfarist values such as distributive equity may justify at least partial internalization of this negative externality.42 For instance, although we would not want to stop the development of autonomous vehicles, distributive concerns may justify providing some compensation for dislocated drivers, a topic to which this Article will return.43

Ultimately, while not all externalities merit internalization, some do. From a traditional welfare perspective, externalities that lead to inefficient resource allocation warrant some form of internalization. In some cases, other values, such as distributive equity, may also justify internalizing (or partially internalizing) externalities.

Externalities are ubiquitous. Prominent sources of externalities from yesteryear, such as gardens, factories, and pig pens, continue to create external benefits and costs for third parties. However, the next two Sections focus on specific kinds of externalities of increasing significance in contemporary times, namely positive and negative externalities from technological innovation.

B. Positive Innovation Externalities

Commentators have long recognized that innovation creates enormous positive externalities.44 While innovators benefit substantially from their own creations, significant benefit slips, uncompensated, to others.45 Innovation spillovers benefit consumers who receive unanticipated consumer surplus, competitors and potential competitors who obtain valuable information, and society at large.46 Because spillovers from innovation are well recognized in the economics and IP literature, this Section’s discussion of positive externalities from innovation will be relatively brief.

Examples of innovation spillovers are legion. Biopharmaceutical companies receive compensation for the drugs they produce, but such drugs generate enormous uncompensated benefits by reducing healthcare costs and increasing social welfare for all. Similarly, Microsoft Office enhances worker productivity and generates significant social value that Microsoft does not capture as private gains. Communication technologies produce enormous spillovers by facilitating conversations, connections, and transactions that the developers of such technologies could never imagine, let alone factor into their development efforts. Network technologies enable positive externalities wherein the value of such networks increases as more users join them.47 Broadly, one of the most important positive externalities of technological innovation is increased economic growth.48

Technologies produce positive externalities not only in the static sense of enhancing present social welfare, but also in the dynamic sense of promoting subsequent innovation.49 Innovators stand on the shoulders of giants, building upon previous innovations.50 Information spillovers drive further innovation, for example when scientists and engineers share information in academic publications and conferences or move between various organizations. Technological investments in one field, such as space exploration, often lead to unexpected applications in other fields, such as solar panels and heart monitors.51

A wide empirical literature has attempted to quantify the positive externalities of investments in research and development.52 One classic study found that the median private rate of return for various industrial innovations was 25%, but the median social rate of return for these innovations was 56%.53 These findings accord with a more recent study reporting that the private rate of return to R&D was 21% while the social rate of return was 55%.54 These empirical findings suggest that the social returns to R&D far outstrip the private returns, indicating the presence of significant positive externalities. Furthermore, they suggest that economic actors may underinvest in R&D relative to the socially optimal level.55

C. Negative Innovation Externalities

Technology, however, also has a dark side. While the economics and IP literature has extensively examined the positive externalities of technology, it has devoted less attention to technology’s negative externalities.56 Technology produces a wide range of negative externalities, including serious harms to physical health and the environment. For example, prescription opioids were once heralded as safe and effective painkillers. However, they have caused an epidemic of addiction and misery involving nearly 500,000 overdose deaths in the United States.57 The opioid crisis cost the U.S. economy $631 billion from 2015 to 2018.58 These costs have largely been external to opioid manufacturers and distributors, though recent litigation has aimed to at least partially internalize these negative externalities.59 For generations, “dirty” technologies, from coal-burning power plants to automobiles, have contributed to arguably the greatest threat facing humanity: global climate change.60 Chemical fertilizers ramped up food production, but they have also enormously increased reactive nitrogen levels throughout the environment.61

Technology also generates negative externalities by harming mental health, well-being, and social connectedness. Numerous studies indicate that adolescents and young adults who spend more time on digital media report lower psychological well-being.62 A 2019 poll by the American Psychiatric Association found that thirty-eight percent of adults view social media usage as harmful to mental health.63 Academic performance is negatively correlated with instant messaging, social networking sites, engaging with smartphones, and use of electronic media more generally.64 Heavy use of digital media is also correlated with a loss of empathic accuracy.65 Developers of computers, Artificial Intelligence, and robots do not bear the psychological costs of users’ loss of human connection and intimacy from interacting with machines instead of people.66

Technology also creates negative externalities by threatening physical safety, privacy, and economic security. One study estimated that social media accounts for about ninety percent of all organized terrorism carried out on the Internet.67 Autonomous weapon systems with no human oversight or input can commit war crimes.68 Drones raise serious privacy concerns, particularly when used by local law enforcement.69 Considering innovation more broadly, financial innovations such as structured financial products and credit default swaps contributed significantly to the Great Recession.70 As noted, a negative externality endemic to the concept of technological progress is that of rendering legacy technologies (and associated jobs) obsolete. For instance, the word-processing programs developed by Microsoft and others led to the demise of the typewriter and displaced those employed by that industry.71 Technology developers profit substantially from their creations, but they are largely insulated from their external costs.

D. Negative Externalities from Patented Technologies

This Article highlights an underappreciated facet of technology’s harmful effects: many technologies that generate negative externalities are patented. In an unsettling irony, the patent system significantly subsidizes the development of technologies that impose uncompensated harms on third parties. To better understand this phenomenon, this Section turns to case studies of three patented technologies that produce substantial negative externalities.

1. Facebook’s “Filter Bubble” and Ideological Polarization

One prominent example of a patented technology generating negative externalities is Facebook’s “filter bubble.”72 Over the past two decades, Facebook has developed innovations to personalize content for users based on their interests and connections. This so-called filter bubble technology has several benefits, including enhancing the relevance of content to users, increasing the stickiness of Facebook’s website, and raising Facebook’s value to advertisers. However, the filter bubble also generates significant harms, particularly in the political sphere. Curated content streams spread misinformation and establish incommensurable “media ecosystems” that expose liberal and conservative users to different universes of information.73 Facebook’s algorithms prioritize content linked to “extreme” reactions or numerous posts, which tend to come from a small but vocal fraction of users.74 Filter bubbles exacerbate political polarization75 and have even been blamed for contributing to the January 6, 2021, U.S. Capitol insurrection.76 Over two dozen U.S. states have filed suit against Facebook for alleged antitrust violations, some of which relate to Facebook’s information-filtering practices.77

While it is difficult to quantify the harms of Facebook’s filter bubble, they are likely substantial. Facebook is the dominant source of news and information for many of its users.78 Filter bubbles foster confirmation biases by providing users with information that supports their existing views and shielding them from opposing perspectives.79 The resulting deterioration of a shared epistemic commons degrades democratic discourse and can lead to political polarization and even violence. Foreign agents have also exploited filter bubbles to spread misinformation; Russia created Facebook pages touting fraudulent information that received 340 million engagements before Facebook deleted them.80 Notwithstanding these harms, Facebook benefits from filter bubbles and has incentives to expand this technology. In the wake of the 2020 U.S. presidential elections, Facebook temporarily altered its algorithms to promote more fact-based information sources, but it soon reversed that decision.81

Notably, Facebook’s filter bubble is patented technology. Among Facebook’s 9,000 patents are several claiming inventions that personalize content based on a user’s interests and connections.82 Take, for example, U.S. Patent No. 9,110,953 B2. This patent covers methods and systems for “Filtering Content in a Social Networking Service,” and it lists Mark Zuckerberg as one of its inventors.83 The patent claims methods and systems by which an algorithm considers various user attributes to deliver highly relevant content.84 The patent consists of sixteen pages of technical diagrams, disclosures, and claims that describe the system’s operation and various preferred embodiments. It discloses several benefits of this invention, which personalizes content for users and enables more targeted advertising.85 However, the patent does not disclose any mechanism for verifying the information provided to users via this algorithm. Furthermore, it contains no discussion of this technology’s wider social ramifications, such as its potential contribution to ideological polarization.

2. Autonomous Vehicles and Job Losses

Autonomous vehicles also generate significant negative externalities. Of course, self-driving vehicles promise significant benefits, such as reducing accidents, enhancing energy efficiency, and increasing mobility for those unable to drive. Alongside these benefits, however, this technology creates external harms for which technology developers are largely unaccountable. For instance, several Tesla cars using its semi-autonomous “Autopilot” driving technology have killed people.86 Lawsuits against Tesla allege design defects; while such lawsuits may force Tesla to internalize some of these costs, Tesla has vigorously denied liability, thus seeking to maintain these costs as externalities. Autonomous vehicles also raise privacy concerns by gathering enormous amounts of data and potentially sharing that data with government entities and third parties.87 At the heart of autonomous vehicles is Artificial Intelligence (AI), which gives rise to a host of negative externalities. As Tesla chief Elon Musk has warned, AI could become “an immortal dictator from which we can never escape.”88

One significant negative externality of AI-based automation in general, and autonomous vehicles in particular, is job losses.89 The threat of automation to replace human workers has attracted significant public policy concern.90 The landscape is complex, as automation can enhance worker productivity and increase demand for skills in some contexts. In other contexts, however, automation eliminates jobs.91 Lower-paid, lower-skilled, and less-educated workers are most susceptible to job losses.92 Focusing on autonomous vehicles, it is estimated that when self-driving cars and trucks reach saturation, job losses among U.S. drivers will amount to 25,000 per month or 300,000 per year.93 The White House Council of Economic Advisors estimates that autonomous vehicles threaten 2.2 to 3.1 million driving-based jobs in the United States.94

Many of the technologies underlying autonomous vehicles are patented.95 An informal search revealed over 135,000 patents or patent applications in the United States mentioning the term “autonomous vehicles.”96 On a massive scale, patent law is encouraging the development of technologies that promise significant benefits but that also impose substantial harms. Take, for example, U.S. Patent No. 9,244,462 B2, which covers “vehicle trajectory planning for autonomous vehicles.”97 This patent, owned by Nissan, claims methods for determining an initial vehicle trajectory and then calculating and executing an optimized vehicle trajectory based on changed parameters. Among other benefits, this method can “smooth out” abrupt changes in direction, such as U-turns, lane changes, and turns at intersections. In doing so, it reduces “occupant discomfort, motion sickness, and decreased confidence in the autonomous system.”98 Not surprisingly, however, amid twelve pages of technical disclosures, there is no mention of the broader social impact of this technology and potential job losses that may arise from autonomous vehicles.

3. Big Data and Government Overreaching

A final example of negative externalities from patented technologies involves methods for analyzing enormous amounts of data, commonly known as big data.99 This innovation has numerous applications, from allowing Target to anticipate consumers’ purchasing needs100 to enabling health officials to track transmissions of coronavirus from people’s cell phones.101 One of the most significant government uses of big data is to predict the occurrence of crime. As Professor Elizabeth Joh has chronicled, law enforcement authorities are using big data and predictive analytics to forecast when and where crime will occur.102 Such predictions allow officials to optimize the allocation of law enforcement resources to various geographic areas. Notably, however, such technology may enable government overreaching that imposes unaccounted-for harms on third parties.103

In particular, predictive policing based on big data may violate Fourth Amendment safeguards against unreasonable searches and seizures. While standard investigative detentions require at least reasonable suspicion based on a totality of the circumstances,104 it is unclear if predictive analysis from big data can support such determinations.105 Furthermore, as Professor Joh argues, predictive policing systems can perpetuate bias: “[R]eliance on arrest rates is surely problematic because arrests themselves are discretionary decisions that, if used as the basis to justify more attention, may simply reinforce unjustified police stereotypes that certain neighborhoods need heavier police attention.”106 Additionally, in borderline cases, police officers may over-rely on prediction models based on the perceived objectivity of the algorithms.107 In short, predictive policing technology can generate negative externalities in the form of biased and excessive arrests.108

Predictive policing technology, which generates negative externalities, is patented. One of these patents is U.S. Patent No. 8,949,164 B1, which covers a “predictive policing system” that uses a crime prediction server, historical crime data, and crime forecasting algorithm to forecast crimes for at least one geographic region.109 Notably, this patented system incorporates the “broken windows” theory of policing. This theory holds that “untended” behavior, such as broken windows and broken-down cars, can undermine community controls.110 (The predictive policing system literally prompts police officers to “scan for broken glass.”)111 This inclusion is troubling in light of recent research debunking the broken windows theory and linking it to increased incidences of stop and frisk, racial profiling, and police misconduct.112 The patent discusses several benefits of the invention, which can help reduce crime and improve the allocation of law enforcement resources.113 At no point, however, does the patent mention the potential harms of this technology, such as the possibility of biased predictions of criminal activity, or offer any correctives. As with the other patented technologies profiled here, inventors benefit from highly valuable exclusive rights, but they are not accountable (in the patent system) for the harms their inventions impose on third parties.

* * *

In sum, technologies generate significant negative externalities. More importantly, patented inventions—which enjoy government-granted exclusive rights—also generate significant negative externalities.114

Of course, it is exceedingly difficult to identify and measure the full scope of externalities associated with any invention.115 While some externalities are obvious, others are quite attenuated from a particular invention. At this level, characterizing an effect as a negative externality is a policy judgment akin to the notion of proximate causation in tort law. Depending on one’s judgment, the negative externalities of Facebook may include work hours lost to procrastination, harms to political discourse, and widespread feelings of ennui from seeing one’s Facebook friends lead seemingly glamorous lives. Additionally, characterizing negative externalities can be highly context specific and subjective. Video games and the consoles that play them are certainly economically significant technologies. But are billions of person-hours spent playing video games wasting time and desensitizing people to violence, or do they provide beneficial amusement, excitement, and education?116 Finally, as should be clear, even if one can properly identify negative externalities, it is very difficult to quantify them in any practical way. It seems doubtful that one could translate the harm from ideological polarization into a dollar amount for purposes of imposing a Pigouvian tax on Facebook’s patented filter bubble technology.117

Yet just because externalities are hard to identify and measure does not mean they do not exist. Nor does it mean that policymakers should simply ignore them. The patent system represents a governmental system for promoting the invention and development of new technologies. In so doing, it rests upon a deep recognition of the significant benefits of technology, particularly its positive externalities. However, the patent system does not seem to recognize, or be capable of effectively remediating, the negative externalities of technology, a phenomenon that the next Part explores.

II. Patent Law’s Externality Asymmetry: Patents Internalize Positive Externalities but Not Negative Externalities

We have seen that technological innovations generate both positive and negative externalities. Externalities are problematic because they can lead to inefficient resource allocation, and the classic prescription is to internalize them by ensuring that decisionmakers account for external benefits and costs when taking some action. Many technologies are patented, which raises the question of what role, if any, patents play in internalizing externalities. This Article finds a surprising result.

This Article argues that patents are asymmetric in their treatment of positive and negative innovation externalities. On the one hand, patents do much to internalize positive innovation externalities; indeed, this is their core function. On the other hand, patents do very little to internalize negative externalities arising from patented technologies. Put differently, the patent system allows patentees to capture a meaningful share of the external benefits of their inventions, but it plays almost no role in holding them accountable for their external costs. This Article refers to this imbalance as patent law’s externality asymmetry. As we will see, this important and overlooked asymmetry impairs the efficient allocation of resources for innovation and undermines social welfare.118 For the time being, however, this and the next Part will flesh out the contours of patent law’s asymmetric internalization of positive and negative innovation externalities.

A. Patents Exist to Internalize Positive Innovation Externalities

The function of internalizing externalities is not foreign to patents; in fact, internalizing positive externalities is their reason for being. The classic justification for patents posits that the technical information at the heart of technology is a public good. This means that the information is both nonrival (one’s consumption of the information does not diminish its availability) and nonexcludable (in the absence of legal protections, it is difficult to prevent others from accessing it).119 As a public good, technical information is subject to undersupply in a fully competitive economy; noninnovating firms could simply copy the inventions of others, thus undermining incentives to invent. Patents allow inventors to exclude free riders, thus mitigating the public goods problem and maintaining incentives to invent.

Put differently, patents internalize positive innovation externalities. Assume that it costs Merck $2.6 billion to develop a new FDA-approved drug and bring it to market.120 In the absence of patents, competing drug companies could simply copy Merck’s drug for free. In this scenario, Merck’s significant R&D expenditures would generate tremendous positive externalities for its competitors (as well as patients and society at large).121 While positive externalities seem like a good thing, they can depress incentives to invent if the inventor does not capture a meaningful share of the benefits produced. If nearly the entire value of Merck’s invention “spills over” to others (including competitors) as positive externalities, Merck would have little incentive to invest in R&D. Patents provide Merck and other inventors with a right to exclude others from practicing an invention for twenty years. As such, they allow inventors to internalize a significant share of the positive externalities of their inventions, thus shoring up incentives to invent.

Of course, patents are not the only mechanism for internalizing positive innovation externalities. Direct public funding, tax breaks, and prizes are among many policy levers that governments employ to enable innovators to capture a greater share of the positive externalities they generate.122 However, patents are the primary legal mechanisms for promoting innovation, and they exist to internalize innovation spillovers.

Intellectual property scholars widely recognize that patents internalize positive externalities from technological development.123 As we will see, even traditional property rights theorists like Harold Demsetz argued that patents enable inventors to internalize some of the external benefits of their inventions, thus bolstering incentives to invent.124 Citing Demsetz, legal scholars Oren Bar-Gill and Gideon Parchomovsky state: “Patents, like other property rights, internalize the positive externalities flowing from inventions and allow the inventor to license the invention to third parties.”125

Of course, the patent system neither aims for nor achieves full internalization of positive externalities. Legal scholars Brett Frischmann and Mark Lemley influentially argue that internalizing all spillovers by giving a patentee complete control over all uses of an invention would decrease, rather than increase, welfare.126 Indeed, the patent system is designed to both internalize some positive externalities and produce others.127 Patents facilitate information spillovers by requiring patentees to disclose their inventions.128 Economist Giovanni Ramello even argues that “the existence of information externalities is the statutory goal of intellectual property.”129 Furthermore, patents generate temporal spillovers through providing widespread access to an invention after a patent expires.130 Returning to the example of Merck, after its patent expires, spillovers increase substantially as generic competition drives down the price of a formerly patented drug.131

That being said, internalizing positive externalities remains the core function of patents. While the patent system does not aim to internalize all positive innovation externalities, it must allow inventors to internalize a meaningful share of spillovers to maintain incentives to invent.

B. Patents Do Little to Internalize Negative Innovation Externalities

Given that patents exist to internalize positive externalities from innovation, it is important to consider their role in internalizing associated negative externalities as well. Here, this Article reveals a striking asymmetry. Patents do very little to internalize technology’s harmful effects on third parties. Patents operate as a one-way ratchet wherein inventors capture some of the external benefits of their inventions but are insulated from their external costs. In minimal and indirect ways, patents can help to internalize or prevent negative innovation externalities. However, their treatment of such negative externalities is a far cry from how they directly internalize positive externalities.

Patented technologies such as Facebook’s filter bubble, autonomous driving innovations, and predictive policing systems generate negative externalities, but patents do very little to internalize them. Patentees of these technologies can profit from practicing these inventions, licensing them to other parties, or suing unauthorized users for infringement. The sweep of patent rights is so broad that Facebook can sue someone for infringement even if Facebook does not practice its invention and even if the infringer did not copy Facebook’s technology. However, if Facebook’s filter bubble degrades political discourse for millions, patents play no role in internalizing this negative externality. The same is true for patented autonomous vehicle innovations, predictive policing systems, and millions of other proprietary technologies.

At this point, it is helpful to address the potential objection that merely inventing and patenting an invention does not create negative externalities, so it would be inapposite for the patent system to do anything to internalize such externalities. According to this objection, negative externalities only arise from using a technology. Under this view, unlike the factory spewing pollution, simply inventing and patenting a new technology does not harm anyone. Notably, this is the flip side of the economic argument that mere invention itself does not produce social benefit; what matters for social benefit is innovation—the act of putting an invention into practice.132 This line of reasoning would contend that any negative externalities from technology—such as political polarization, job losses, or unreasonable searches and seizures—only arise when an invention is practiced rather than simply invented. Put differently, the inventor who patents a predictive policing system does not harm others; the police department that uses that system to violate constitutional rights harms others. In this light, because merely inventing a technology does not create external costs, it would be inapposite to expect the patent system to internalize those costs.

However, this argument is misplaced for several reasons. To begin, many inventors patent their technologies and practice them, thus “directly” causing negative externalities. This is the case, for instance, with filter bubble technology, which Facebook developed, patented, and then deployed on its network.

More importantly, the patent system is entirely predicated on allowing inventors to internalize positive externalities from real-world use of their inventions based simply on what their patent disclosures potentially enable. Under the patent quid pro quo, patentees need only provide an enabling disclosure of their technology, yet they get exclusive rights over all physical uses of that technology.133 A patentee does not need to practice an invention to assert exclusive rights against other parties. Furthermore, a patentee does not even have to actually enable another party’s use of an invention to sue for infringement; independent inventors who did not copy (or even know about) a patented invention are still liable for infringement.134 Furthermore, patentees have exclusive rights over uses of their technologies that they could not even foresee, as long as those uses fall within the scope of their claims.135 In essence, the sweep of exclusive rights encompasses not only what patentees actually enable, but what they potentially enable. It may seem unfair to hold a patentee accountable when an unrelated entity utilizes a patented technology in a way that harms third parties. By this token, it may seem unfair to provide the patentee with a share of the upside when an independent inventor utilizes a patented technology in a way that benefits third parties. Indeed, some have argued for limiting patent infringement liability to instances of direct copying.136 Within the current framework, however, merely obtaining a patent gives a patentee a claim on third-party benefits from real-world use of an invention. As such, it would appear consistent to also hold a patentee accountable for some third-party costs based on real-world use of that invention.

It is also helpful to briefly address the objection that the patent system aims to promote technological progress, so it should not internalize negative innovation externalities. After all, doing so would chill inventive activity. This Article addresses this objection more fully below,137 but for now it is sufficient to say that this argument misunderstands the objectives of the patent system. While the patent system seeks to promote technological progress, it does not aim to do so at all costs. Rather, it aims to maximize efficiency in the allocation of resources for innovation. Maximizing efficiency, moreover, must entail considering costs as well as benefits, including positive and negative externalities.

In some minimal and indirect ways, patent law can internalize negative externalities (or prevent them from arising in the first place). First, the patent system has applied certain requirements of patentability to deny patents on “immoral” inventions, which presumably have significant potential to create negative externalities. For example, historically the patent office and courts applied the doctrine of moral utility to deny patents on inventions that contravened public morals.138 Under this doctrine, “a new invention to poison people, or to promote debauchery, or to facilitate private assassination” would fail the moral utility doctrine and not receive a patent.139 However, the moral utility doctrine has largely fallen into desuetude because of institutional competence limitations: the Patent and Trademark Office (PTO) and courts are not arbiters of public morality.140 While it had some historical bite, the moral utility doctrine does little these days to deny patents on so-called “immoral” inventions and reduce associated negative externalities.

Another requirement of patentability—patentable subject matter—also does little to reduce negative externalities. An invention must satisfy the threshold requirement of patentable subject matter in order to be eligible for patenting.141 On rare occasions, patent authorities have excluded certain classes of inventions from patentable subject matter, ostensibly on moral grounds. For instance, in the late 1990s, the PTO denied a patent application claiming human-animal chimeras.142 While it stated that this invention did not constitute patentable subject matter, lurking in the background were moral concerns over this technology. Unease about cloning technology and patenting humans led to a statutory carveout in the 2011 America Invents Act establishing that claims directed to or encompassing a human organism are not patentable subject matter.143 While restrictions on patent eligibility could, in theory, deny patents on immoral inventions likely to generate high negative externalities, such exclusions are quite limited. Moral concerns play a very small role in narrowing patent eligibility in U.S. patent law, particularly compared to other jurisdictions.144

Second, in an indirect way, the patent system can reduce negative externalities by constraining the dissemination of harmful or undesirable inventions. While patents aim to promote invention, observers have long recognized that too much patent protection can have the opposite effect.145 Innovations are often subject to multiple, overlapping patents, and the need to clear all of these exclusive rights may be prohibitively expensive. Scholars have extensively explored the innovation-dampening effects of so-called “anticommons” and “patent thickets.”146 In a provocative article, Professors Chris Cotropia and Jim Gibson argue that the ability of patents to inhibit innovation can have some unexpected benefits.147 In particular, patents can impede innovation and dissemination of technologies in harmful industries. As a descriptive matter, however, several of the industries that Cotropia and Gibson examine, such as biotechnology, seem to be thriving quite well with robust patent protection. Additionally, as a normative matter, it is far from clear that industries like biotechnology are ones that we would want to suppress, a point that the authors recognize.148 Cotropia and Gibson offer a valuable insight that policymakers can use patents to restrain innovation in undesirable areas. However, as presently constituted, the patent system does not do much in this regard in any targeted fashion.

In sum, while patents exist to internalize positive externalities associated with technology, they do very little to internalize negative externalities. This is particularly surprising in light of influential economic theory contending that property rights play an important role in internalizing both kinds of externalities, a topic that the next Part examines.

III. Exploring Patent Law’s Externality Asymmetry: Comparing Physical Property Rights and Patents

To gain greater insight into how patents govern cutting-edge technologies, this Part turns to a classic legal regime: property rights in land. Comparing patents to physical property rights reveals that patent law is quite singular in internalizing positive externalities while doing relatively little to internalize negative externalities. Foundational economic theory suggests that property rights arise for the precise purpose of internalizing externalities. Like patents, physical property rights allow resource owners to internalize positive externalities from productive activity, thus encouraging such activity. Physical property rights are symmetrical in that they also internalize negative externalities in several ways: they mitigate tragedies of the commons, facilitate efficiency-maximizing negotiations between property owners and those affected by their actions, and impose duties on property owners to limit harms to others. As this Part will show, however, these mechanisms largely do not apply to patents. This juxtaposition casts into sharper relief the unique incapacity of patents to internalize negative externalities.

In comparing patents and physical property rights, this Article takes no position in the long-running debate over whether intellectual property is property.149 Rather, it advances the uncontroversial view that these bodies of law are similar in some ways but different in others. On the one hand, both patents and property rights in land confer exclusive rights. On the other hand, the subject matter of patents is nonrival, which clearly differs from the rivalrous subject matter of physical property rights.150 Furthermore, this Article reveals another overlooked difference: while physical property rights symmetrically internalize positive and negative externalities, patents asymmetrically internalize only positive externalities.

In response to those who would question the value of comparing patents and physical property rights, this Article offers three reasons. First, foundational economic theory holds that property rights (which at least nominally include patents)151 serve to internalize externalities.152 Second, the most influential expositor of this economic theory specifically argued that patents internalize externalities just like property rights in land (though this Article argues to the contrary).153 Third, even if one believes that patents and physical property rights are completely unrelated, comparing these two regulatory regimes reveals idiosyncratic features of patents (and physical property rights) that scholars and policymakers have largely overlooked.

Where excessive externalities are a problem, law is often the solution.154 Many bodies of law can be understood as mechanisms to internalize externalities.155 Environmental regulation forces polluters to at least partially internalize the harms they impose on third parties. Tort law imposes liability on negligent actors who injure others.156 Tax law is a major mechanism for internalizing externalities. So-called Pigouvian taxes levy taxes on activities and substances that adversely affect others, from pollution to sugary drinks.157

Among all legal fields, property rights play a particularly prominent role in internalizing externalities.158 Indeed, as influential economist Harold Demsetz famously stated, “[P]roperty rights develop to internalize externalities when the gains of internalization become larger than the cost of internalization.”159 For Demsetz, property rights emerge precisely when new or increased externalities emerge, thus rendering the benefits of internalizing some externalities worth the costs, including the costs of delineating and enforcing property rights.160

A. How Physical Property Rights Internalize Positive Externalities

Physical property rights play an important role in internalizing positive externalities. This comparison reveals deep parallels with patent law, which, as we have seen, performs this function as well.161 Examples of property rights internalizing spillovers are numerous. In the absence of property rights in land, a farmer’s cultivation of crops would generate enormous positive externalities for others. Given that the farmer lacked a right to exclude, strangers could simply walk onto “her” land and take those crops for free. Exploitation of such positive externalities, a classic case of free riding, would significantly decrease the farmer’s incentive to cultivate crops.162 Property rights in land allow farmers to exclude such free riders, allowing them to literally reap what they sow.

Demsetz used a similar example to illustrate how property rights internalized externalities among Indigenous Canadians of the Labrador Peninsula.163 Originally, Indigenous Canadians were unconstrained in where they could hunt game. With the emergence of the fur trade, the value of fur increased substantially, and some individuals began investing time and effort in raising game. Given the increased value of furs, such cultivation generated a significant positive externality for others, particularly for poachers who could take the game for free. As Demsetz argued, the rise in the value of fur led to the recognition of private property rights in land. It became worthwhile for Indigenous Canadians to assert a right to exclude poachers from their land, thus internalizing the spillovers from husbandry (and, relatedly, decreasing negative externalities from poaching).164 Here again, private property rights allowed people to reap what they sowed, thus maintaining incentives to engage in productive activity. In this respect, physical property rights clearly parallel patents, which also confer exclusive rights to prevent free riding and maintain incentives to invent.

B. How Physical Property Rights Internalize Negative Externalities

In addition to internalizing positive externalities from land use, physical property rights internalize negative externalities in several ways. In so doing, they diverge from patents, which are largely ineffectual in internalizing the negative externalities of technological innovation. While physical property rights do not internalize all negative externalities, they mitigate externalities associated with the tragedy of the commons, facilitate transactions whereby parties can negotiate efficient resource allocations, and create duties for property owners to limit harms to others.

1. Mitigating Overuse in the Tragedy of the Commons

First, property rights reduce negative externalities associated with the tragedy of the commons.165 Consider a fishing pond open to all members of a community. Each person’s fishing imposes a negative externality on other community members, as it leaves fewer fish for everyone else. Furthermore, in the absence of property rights, everyone has an incentive to fish as much and as fast as possible. The result is overconsumption and depletion of resources, a phenomenon Garrett Hardin famously described as the tragedy of the commons.166 Property rights are a means to internalize negative externalities and mitigate this tragedy. One option would be to grant one party property rights to the pond. That individual could rationalize the consumption of fish either directly or through licensing other parties. Another option, more suited to industrial fishing, would be to allocate private harvesting rights to commercial fishing operations as a fraction of some “total allowable catch.”167 In both approaches, property rights help parties conserve resources and reduce the negative effects of their behavior on others.

Notably, property rights reduce negative externalities not only across parties but also across time. In a communal fishery, each person’s fishing creates a negative externality for others. Additionally, given the incentive to fish as rapidly as possible, such actions also impose a negative externality on future generations, whose fish supply will be depleted. Private property rights internalize this temporal negative externality as well. If an individual owns a productive resource like a fishery or farm, she has greater incentive to conserve it so that it does not deplete over time. As Demsetz observed, “[A]n owner of a private right to use land acts as a broker whose wealth depends on how well he takes into account the competing claims of the present and the future.”168

2. Lowering Transaction Costs and Promoting Efficiency-Enhancing Negotiations

Second, property rights lower transaction costs between decisionmakers and affected parties, enabling voluntary negotiations to internalize externalities. While introducing private property rights internalizes some externalities, many others still persist. Granting an individual property rights over a parcel of land will encourage her to cultivate it judiciously to maximize its private value.169 In doing so, however, she may still impose negative externalities on her neighbors. For instance, a private landowner may store water on her land by damming a river, thus creating a negative externality for a downstream party who now has less access to water.170 Here, property rights help internalize externalities by facilitating voluntary transactions between landowners and parties affected by their decisions. If the social returns to free-flowing water outweigh the private returns of a dam, the downstream party could pay the upstream landowner to not erect the dam, thus mitigating this externality and achieving a socially efficient allocation of resources. Through voluntary transactions, a decisionmaker can take into account an effect that would otherwise be an unaccounted-for externality. By assigning ownership over a resource, property rights enable such transactions between a party who controls that resource and those affected by it. In this example, if the upstream land were held in a commons rather than subject to individual property rights, negotiations to prevent building an upstream dam would be much more complicated.171

As Demsetz recognized, the role of property rights in facilitating transactions and internalizing externalities represents an application of the Coase theorem.172 As conventionally understood, the Coase theorem posits that in the absence of transaction costs, parties will negotiate to achieve efficient allocations of resources.173 Imagine someone operated a pig pen that annoyed his neighbors. If the private returns of the pig pen were less than the social returns, the neighbors could raise enough money to “buy off” the pig pen owner and cease the offending activity. In such a situation, voluntary negotiations would lead to the socially efficient result that internalized the negative externality.174 In other words, without transaction costs, parties will negotiate to achieve an efficient allocation of resources regardless of the initial assignment of entitlements.175 In the real world, of course, transaction costs are not zero. However, as Demsetz describes, property rights reduce transaction costs by allocating control over particular resources to specific owners. In the absence of clearly defined rights of control, bargaining to internalize externalities would be much more difficult and, in some cases, impossible. Property rights lower transaction costs, and “allowing transactions increases the degree to which internalization takes place.”176

3. Establishing Duties to Limit Harms to Others

Third, moving beyond the areas on which Demsetz focused, physical property rights also internalize externalities directly by establishing duties on landowners to limit harms to others. This function is best illustrated by the doctrine of nuisance.177 The guiding principle of nuisance law is “sic utere tuo ut alienum non laedas,” or “one should use one’s own property in such a way as not to injure the property of another.”178 Nuisance law reflects the principle that property rights confer not only the right to exclude but also the duty to refrain from unreasonably interfering with the property rights of others.179 Nuisance law has significant implications for internalizing negative externalities, particularly in the environmental context. For example, it can enjoin the operation of an oil refinery that emits nauseating fumes and odors, thus internalizing this externality.180

The externality-internalizing function of nuisance law has particular traction given the ubiquity of property rights in land. As Coase noted, just as it takes two to tango, it also takes two to have a nuisance: one party to engage in behavior and another to be bothered by it.181 Thus, both the factory belching smoke and the neighbor bothered by it are “but-for” causes of a nuisance. Due to the reciprocal nature of nuisance, one only has duties to another property owner if there is another property owner to be bothered. This insight foregrounds another aspect of property rights that is highly relevant to internalizing externalities: property rights are everywhere, and just about everyone has a neighbor. Almost all land is owned by someone, and all property owners (in jurisdictions recognizing nuisance) have a right to enjoy their property free from unreasonable interference. Indeed, real property is famously difficult to abandon, partly to prevent people from avoiding the duties of landownership.182 The ubiquity of property rights supports a pervasive system of internalizing externalities. The world is literally covered with rights to not be unreasonably bothered by one’s neighbors.

Physical property rights internalize negative externalities in other ways as well. Under the traditional English rule of absolute ownership of groundwater, anyone owning land above an aquifer could withdraw as much water as desired.183 Such a regime enabled significant negative externalities, and the American rule of reasonable use mitigates those externalities by establishing that wasteful uses of water that harm others are unreasonable and unlawful.184 Turning to another example, the doctrine of lateral support prohibits landowners from manipulating their soil in a way that would cause their neighbor’s land to subside.185 In so doing, this doctrine internalizes the negative externalities arising from how an owner uses her land. Similarly, the doctrine of subjacent support imposes a duty on owners of surface and subsurface rights to not erode property owned by the other.186 The doctrine would impose liability on the owner of mineral rights whose mining caused the surface land (owned by another party) to cave in. Here again, physical property rights create duties to internalize negative externalities.187

Internalizing externalities is a core function of physical property rights, and in some contexts, it is their reason for being. Like patents, physical property rights internalize positive externalities and provide incentives for owners to acquire and use resources productively. Additionally, as this Section has explored, physical property rights internalize negative externalities in several prominent ways. In so doing, physical property rights encourage and compel property owners to think about and mitigate the harmful effects of their actions on others.

C. Patent Law’s Limited Ability to Internalize Negative Externalities

As we have seen, patent law is very limited in its ability to internalize negative externalities related to innovation.188 This limitation is even starker when comparing patents to physical property rights. Both kinds of exclusive rights internalize positive externalities. But whether by design or nature of the subject matter protected, the traditional mechanisms by which physical property rights internalize negative externalities largely do not apply to patents.

1. Patents Do Not Avert Tragedies of the Commons, and They Encourage Rapidly Exploiting Innovations

First, patents are inapposite to curtailing consumption of technology to avert a tragedy of the commons. Recall that in the physical realm, property rights play a salutary role in internalizing negative externalities associated with communally owned property.189 Individual property rights help prevent overexploitation and resource depletion associated with the tragedy of the commons. However, patents cover nonrival resources such as technical information; accordingly, the tragedy of the commons does not apply.190 For instance, given that the chemical formula for a drug is nonrival, this informational asset is not subject to overconsumption.191 Patents thus do not internalize negative externalities associated with the tragedy of the commons because that tragedy does not arise. In fact, patents actually create negative externalities because they introduce artificial scarcity in otherwise inexhaustible resources.192

At first glance, this seems like an odd example to illustrate that patents, unlike physical property rights, do not internalize negative externalities. Indeed, the fact that patents do not internalize negative externalities associated with the tragedy of the commons may seem inapposite because such tragedies do not apply to nonrival assets. At a deeper level, however, this comparison reveals important differences in the ways that physical property rights and patents affect consumption and exploitation of protected resources.

While physical property rights encourage owners to conserve their resources (thus internalizing externalities), patents provide the opposite incentive: to exploit technologies as rapidly as possible. Such rapid exploitation may exacerbate negative externalities associated with patented inventions.193 Recall that physical property rights internalize negative externalities associated with time. In the absence of exclusive rights, individuals have an incentive to exploit a resource as fast as possible, thereby discounting the interests of future generations. Private property rights mitigate this negative externality, encouraging owners to conserve their resources for the benefit of both their later selves and future owners. Patent law provides the opposite incentive. Rather than promote conservation of technologies, the expiration of patents after twenty years encourages patentees to exploit their inventions as fast as possible before they fall into the public domain. Of course, for a variety of reasons, many patentees do not rush to exploit their inventions during the patent term.194 However, given the time-limited nature of exclusive rights, patents create an incentive for patentees to exploit their inventions quickly.

In general, this incentive to exploit inventions quickly seems like a feature rather than a bug. Given that technical information cannot be overconsumed, and in light of the constitutional objective of promoting technological progress, we generally want patentees to move quickly to churn out patented medicines, software applications, and other technologies.

However, the incentive to exploit technology quickly can also exacerbate negative externalities from innovation. Physical property rights have a conservative character in that they encourage owners to consume their resources judiciously. After all, owners bear the costs of overconsuming their resources, and property rights encourage measured resource exploitation. Patents, if anything, provide the opposite incentive: to rush headlong into developing and commercializing technologies as fast as possible. Such rapid exploitation is not conducive to unhurried considerations of the potential harms a technology imposes on others. This accelerated mindset is exacerbated by patent rules encouraging inventors to file patent applications as soon as possible after conceiving of an invention.195 Liberal disclosure requirements that do not require inventors to build physical prototypes of their technologies196 and novelty rules that punish patentees who file too late197 push patent applicants to file early,198 while their technologies may be quite embryonic. Early filing contributes to a host of well-recognized problems in the patent system, including the underdevelopment of patented inventions.199 Additionally, early filing coupled with rapid exploitation of technologies before the patent term expires discourages patentees from engaging in measured considerations of the third-party harms of their inventions and attempts to mitigate them.

In sum, patents do not internalize negative externalities associated with the tragedy of the commons because of the nonrival nature of technology. More importantly, they do not promote the conservative and judicious use of owned resources in the way that physical property rights do. Rather, they encourage faster and wider exploitation of technology in ways that are not conducive to internalizing negative innovation externalities.

2. High Transaction Costs Undermine Patents’ Ability to Facilitate Efficiency-Enhancing Negotiations

Patents are also limited in their ability to internalize externalities by facilitating transactions between patentees and parties harmed by their inventions. As discussed, physical property rights can internalize externalities by lowering transaction costs and thus facilitating voluntary exchanges between property owners and those affected by their decisions.200 Thus, if a landowner prevents a river on his property from flowing downstream, an affected downstream party could pay that landowner to release the water. In this sense, property rights facilitate voluntary transactions that lead to more efficient resource allocation. To be sure, a wide literature explores how patents also lower transaction costs and facilitate voluntary transactions involving protected technology.201 The classic example is the patent licensing agreement, in which patents facilitate the packaging and transfer of technology from a rightsholder to another party for exploitation. However, this kind of transaction facilitates the affirmative use of technology (thus helping the patentee capture positive externalities) rather than compelling a patentee to cease using or to redesign a technology, which may internalize negative externalities.

Notably, Demsetz specifically argued that patents—like physical property rights—helped internalize externalities by promoting transactions. He observed that innovations generate both benefits and harms for third parties that are external to innovators. However, patents can help facilitate voluntary transactions to internalize those externalities: “A new idea makes an old one obsolete and another old one more valuable. These effects will not be directly taken into account, but they can be called to the attention of the originator of the new idea through market negotiations.”202 Thus, someone harmed by a new technology could, in theory, negotiate with the owner of that technology (the patentee) to suppress it. Consistent with his view of property rights in land, Demsetz argued that patents can internalize externalities by lowering transaction costs between owners of inventions and those affected by those inventions. In discussing patents, he stated, “All problems of externalities are closely analogous to those which arise in the land ownership example. The relevant variables are identical.”203

However, the ability of patents to facilitate negotiations to internalize negative externalities faces significant complications. In principle, patents do reduce transaction costs by assigning control over a technology to a single party. People affected by that technology can negotiate with a single patentee, resulting in lower transaction costs relative to a world in which patents did not exist. In the absence of patents, anybody could practice a given technology, and the cost of negotiating with all practitioners of a technology (including new ones as they emerge) would be prohibitively high. However, the nature of patent rights complicates the ability of such negotiations to internalize negative externalities. In the physical realm, negotiations with a polluting factory owner could conceivably lead to the owner agreeing to reduce pollution in exchange for a fee. However, negotiations with the holder of a patent on pollution-generating technology would play out much differently. An affected party could negotiate so that the patentee would not practice or license the technology. But to truly internalize externalities, the patentee would also have to commit to suing infringers, including independent inventors, who also practiced that technology. An agreement to not only refrain from using or licensing an invention but also affirmatively sue others would significantly increase the compensation that patentees would demand from those affected by their technologies. Additionally, such an agreement would raise significant difficulties of monitoring and enforcement. Such complications of an affirmative duty would undermine negotiations between a patentee and those harmed by a technology to internalize negative externalities.

In addition to this theoretical complication, bargaining with patentees to internalize externalities faces a significant practical difficulty: high transaction costs. As Demsetz observed, when transaction costs are high, internalization of externalities is not feasible even with properly delineated property rights.204 A primary way that transaction costs increase is with the number of parties involved in negotiations. Pollution cases, which involve large numbers of affected parties, are a classic example.205

On the “victim” side, patented technologies can impose negative externalities on an enormous number of people. The large number of victims raises coordination costs and jeopardizes negotiations aimed at internalizing those externalities. In the land context, imagine that a factory belches pollution that bothers not just a single neighbor, but all the residents of a town. Here, the large number of harmed parties raises transaction costs and hampers negotiations aimed at achieving efficient outcomes.206 In the technological context, this dynamic is amplified by several orders of magnitude. Unlike a rivalrous plot of land, technology is nonrivalrous and scales easily. A patented technology, such as Facebook’s filter bubble, can impose externalities on millions (or billions) of people. It would be prohibitively expensive for so many people to coordinate, say, a payment to Facebook to prevent it from deploying this technology (and committing to sue anyone else who used it). In addition to the sheer problem of numerosity, such collective efforts are subject to free riding, monitoring, and policing costs, which would be greatly amplified given the large number of people involved.207

In the real property realm, empirical studies have shown that large numbers of victims can overcome coordination problems, particularly when they are members of a shared community.208 However, coordination costs are much higher when technologies—rather than activities on a particular parcel of land—harm individuals. Although uses of land can impose negative externalities on a wide swath of people, geographic proximity largely constrains those effects; after all, smoke, noise, and odor only carry so far.209 This is not the case for patented technologies, which can generate negative externalities unconstrained by location. Furthermore, the large number of people harmed by a technology would, in general, share no communal or social bond that could assist in massively coordinating a response to a negative externality.210

Consider, for example, the legions of professional drivers who may be displaced by patented autonomous vehicle technology. As mentioned, the White House Council of Economic Advisors predicts that autonomous vehicles threaten 2.2 to 3.1 million driving-based jobs in the United States.211 It would be virtually impossible for all of those drivers to coordinate a payment to owners of autonomous driving patents to cease use of this technology. Even if there were a collective effort to organize payment, many drivers would likely not participate and seek to free ride on the contributions of others.

Transaction costs are also problematic on the innovator side. Demsetz posits that persons adversely affected by a technology could negotiate with the technology “originator” to internalize externalities.212 However, it is unclear how this would actually work in practice. Even if professional drivers could coordinate amongst themselves, with whom would they have to negotiate? A logical starting point would be manufacturers and distributors of autonomous vehicles. These companies likely invented and patented some technologies used in their vehicles while licensing some patents from others. However, numerous firms are developing autonomous vehicles, and negotiating with all of them raises transaction costs. In the land context, this would be akin to residents having to negotiate not with one factory belching pollution, but with multiple factories owned by different parties. In addition to sheer numerosity, holdouts would also hamper negotiations—if nine autonomous vehicle manufacturers agreed to be bought off, the tenth would have an incentive to hold out for supranormal compensation.213

Moving beyond manufacturers, if professional drivers sought to negotiate with actual patentees, the problem gets worse. Most technological products comprise numerous (sometimes, thousands) of patented components.214 For example, an autonomous driving system may rely on dozens of different patented technologies covering sensors, processors, methods for calculating trajectories, and user interfaces. If autonomous vehicles threaten to displace human drivers, with which patentees must drivers transact to internalize that externality? It would be very difficult to identify a “core” basket of patented technologies that aggrieved parties would have to suppress to truly inhibit autonomous vehicles. Identifying such a core would be particularly difficult given that for most technical functions, any number of alternate technologies (patented or unpatented) could serve as adequate substitutes.

In sum, while patents may reduce transaction costs, the prospect of negotiating to internalize negative externalities would be virtually impossible in many real-world settings.215 Unlike the factory belching pollution, patented technologies impose negative externalities on enormous numbers of unconnected people unconstrained by geography. Even if such large numbers of people could coordinate, they would likely have to deal with numerous technology distributors and/or patentees to effectively internalize externalities. Rather than a one-to-one exchange, negotiations over negative innovation externalities are many-to-many transactions that are highly difficult in the real world.

The persistence of high transaction costs even in the presence of patents reveals an important Coasean insight. The Coase theorem, as conventionally understood, posits that in a world of zero transaction costs, parties will bargain to an efficient outcome regardless of the initial allocation of entitlements.216 However, Coase’s overarching insight is that when transaction costs are nontrivial (as is overwhelmingly the case in the real world), parties will not always bargain to achieve an efficient outcome, and the initial allocation of entitlements can matter considerably.217 Given the infeasibility of Coasean bargaining to internalize the externalities of patented inventions, the initial allocation of entitlements is likely to be quite sticky. And as far as the patent system is concerned, the initial allocation of entitlements allows patentees to claim a share of the upside of their inventions while not accounting for any of their external costs.

3. Patents Do Not Establish Duties to Limit Harms to Others

Unlike physical property rights, patents lack a more direct mechanism for internalizing externalities: they impose no duties on patentees to limit harms to others. Recall that property rights in land establish several duties for landowners that limit their negative externalities.218 This is evident in doctrines governing nuisance, groundwater, lateral support, and subjacent support. There are no corresponding duties in patent law.219 Patents confer a right to exclude others from practicing an invention,220 but no duties to limit or even consider the harms of one’s invention on third parties. As discussed above, patent law’s historical requirement of moral utility, which can somewhat play this function, is largely a dead letter.221

Going further, there is no widely distributed right to not be harmed by patented technologies. The law of nuisance creates both duties and rights. In Hohfeldian terms, a landowner’s duty to refrain from interfering with the property of others is the “jural correlative” of another landowner’s right to be free from interference.222 Coupled with the fact that virtually all land is owned by someone, the right to be free from interference creates a powerful constraint against property owners imposing externalities on others. This system of rights and duties has no analog in patent law. While nearly all land is owned (and thus implicates a right to be free from undue interference), there is no widely distributed “anti-technology” right to be free from unreasonable harms from technology—patented or otherwise.223 Such a right, held widely, could do much to compel the internalization of negative innovation externalities. Of course, there are other bodies of law that limit what one can do with a patented invention, just as there are other bodies of law that limit what one can do on one’s land. However, unlike physical property rights, there is little intrinsic to patents themselves that performs this externality-internalizing function.

* * *

Comparing physical property rights and patents casts in starker relief the uniqueness of patent law’s externality asymmetry. Patents exist to internalize positive externalities from technological innovation. In so doing, they help shore up incentives to invent. Physical property rights serve a similar function; they encourage landowners to reap what they sow by allowing them to internalize positive externalities from productive land use. Physical property rights are symmetrical in that they also help internalize negative externalities through several mechanisms. Patents, however, are asymmetric in lacking these mechanisms. Patents do not resolve tragedies of the commons; rather, they encourage rapid exploitation of technologies in a way that can exacerbate negative externalities. Patents do not realistically facilitate transactions whereby technology owners and those harmed by technology can negotiate to internalize externalities. Unlike physical property rights, patents create no duties to limit harmful effects on others.

Crucially, these arguments do not depend on accepting the contested view that intellectual property is property. Foundational economic theory associates exclusive rights, in general, with internalizing both positive and negative externalities. Furthermore, the principal expositor of that theory specifically argued that patents and physical property rights operate similarly in this regard.224 This Article, however, argues that this received wisdom is misguided. It next turns to normatively assessing patent law’s externality asymmetry.

IV. Normative Assessment of Patent Law’s Externality Asymmetry

While patents promote the invention of remarkable technologies—from smartphones to medicines—they do little to internalize the negative externalities that technologies inevitably produce. Having established the descriptive claim that patents asymmetrically internalize positive but not negative externalities, this Part turns to a normative assessment of this asymmetry. To do so, this Part first explores the overarching normative objectives of the patent system. It argues that the patent system aims to maximize efficiency in the allocation of resources for innovation rather than maximize innovation at all costs. It rejects the argument that patent law’s externality asymmetry is benign or even beneficial, and it contends that this asymmetry contributes to a host of social ills. In particular, this asymmetry impairs innovative efficiency, distributive equity, and fairness.

A. The Normative Objectives of Patent Law

To assess patent law’s externality asymmetry, it is useful to first clarify the overarching normative objectives of patent law. The Constitution authorizes Congress to establish a patent system “To promote the Progress of Science and useful Arts.”225 As courts and commentators have long observed, this provision establishes a broadly utilitarian objective for the patent system.226 Patents exist not to reward individual inventors but to advance society-wide technological progress.227 With this in mind, several points are worth exploring in greater detail.

First, it is important to clarify that the overarching aim of the patent system is to maximize efficiency in the allocation of resources for innovation, not to maximize innovation itself. It is universally recognized that patents exist to promote innovation.228 However, it is also clear that the patent system does not aim to maximize innovation at all costs. After all, we do not want all of our social resources devoted to innovation to the exclusion of providing food, shelter, and other goods. If maximizing innovation were the objective of patent law, it could do much more to incentivize inventive activity. For example, it could couple exclusive rights with government grants, give tax breaks to patentees, or lower the threshold for obviousness to induce the creation of more incremental advances.229 Rather than aiming to promote innovation at all costs, patents aim to promote innovation in a way that maximizes social welfare.230 As economists would say, the patent system aims to maximize efficiency in the allocation of resources for innovation.231

To achieve this efficient allocation, the patent system enables a market-based system of technological development. Economists, including Demsetz, have long argued that markets allocate resources more efficiently than centralized planning.232 It would be exceedingly difficult for a government to know the socially optimal mix of technologies to invent and develop at any given time. However, as economist Friedrich Hayek famously observed, markets and prices harness information from millions of producers and consumers about preferred resource allocations.233 The patent system exploits the informational and efficiency advantages of markets by establishing property rights in new inventions.234 By conferring exclusive rights upon inventors, the patent system enables markets for technology and allows voluntary transactions (mediated by prices) to guide the production and distribution of new inventions. The assumption (or hope) is that the market will allocate resources efficiently, at least better than any other alternative.

However, markets sometimes fail. As economists since at least Pigou have recognized, private returns (prices) of activities do not always accurately signal social returns and capture all relevant costs and benefits. And one important reason why markets fail—and prices do not signal social returns—is externalities.235 Indeed, the patent system is itself born from one form of market failure (positive externalities), and it is ironic that it ignores another (negative externalities). Again, patent law does not seek to maximize technological innovation at all costs; social costs such as the opportunity cost of allocating resources to innovation instead of other pursuits are part of the efficiency calculus. This Article highlights another important cost that the patent calculus overlooks: negative externalities from patented inventions.

Second, it is clear that the patent system does not exist to reward individual inventors. The Supreme Court has long disavowed that the patent system aims to maximize private gains, emphasizing the public nature of patent rights. In Graham v. John Deere, the Court noted that Thomas Jefferson, the architect of the U.S. patent system, “rejected a natural-rights theory in intellectual property rights and clearly recognized the social and economic rationale of the patent system.”236 More recently, the Court reaffirmed this view by likening patents to “public franchises” where the government “take[s] from the public rights of immense value, and bestow[s] them upon the patentee.”237 A system that allows patentees to internalize positive externalities of their inventions but does little to internalize negative externalities seems well designed to maximize patentee profits. But this has never been a goal of the patent system.

Third, while efficiency represents the dominant objective of patent law, other values such as distributive equity and fairness have some normative claim on the patent system. The patent system reveals a commitment to distributive values in policies that widen access to patented technologies, encourage the development of technologies that serve marginalized communities, and broaden participation by underrepresented inventors.238 Commentators have also persuasively argued that fairness provides a foundational justification for the patent system.239 In a broader sense, like property law and other legal regimes, patent law must be attentive to norms of fairness to maintain social esteem and compliance.240 Thus, while efficiency represents the most prominent normative lens through which to evaluate the patent system, nonwelfarist values like distributive equity and fairness are highly relevant as well.

B. Potential Advantages of Patent Law’s Externality Asymmetry

Some might argue that patent law’s internalization of positive but not negative innovation externalities is not problematic. They may even go further to argue that this reflects a well-functioning patent system. After all, robust incentives to invent seem to advance the constitutional objective of the patent system, which is to promote innovation. According to this view, forcing patentees to internalize the negative externalities of their inventions would chill invention and undermine this aim.

As discussed above, however, this argument misunderstands the goals of the patent system. The patent system seeks not to promote innovation at all costs but to provide for the efficient allocation of resources for innovation. Efficiency must consider the benefits and costs of technological development, and negative externalities must be part of the calculus. More broadly, the impetus to encourage invention at all costs betrays a narrow and misguided view that technology is invariably a net social positive and that more technology is always better. However, technology is not costless. While technological designs may be nonrival, the scarce inputs that create them are not;241 labor, physical capital, and financial capital devoted to innovation cannot be used for other worthy social ends. Furthermore, as this Article has argued, some technologies generate significant negative externalities that reduce (and perhaps even wholly outweigh) their contribution to social welfare.

C. The Harms of Patent Law’s Externality Asymmetry

This Section argues that patent law’s externality asymmetry contributes to a host of social ills. It will primarily examine how patent law’s ineffectiveness in internalizing negative externalities undermines efficiency, the dominant objective animating the patent system. In short, patents may overincentivize innovation, incentivize the wrong mix of innovations, and provide suboptimal incentives for technological design. Moving beyond efficiency concerns, this Section then argues that patent law’s externality asymmetry also undermines distributive equity, as those bearing the costs of innovation externalities are often underresourced relative to patentees. Finally, this Section argues that patent law’s externality asymmetry impairs fairness by allowing inventors to foist external costs on others while internalizing external benefits.

1. Efficiency

Most importantly, patent law’s externality asymmetry undermines patent law’s primary objective of innovative efficiency.242 At a broad level, this deficiency manifests in two ways. First, the inability of patents to internalize negative externalities drives a wedge between private returns and social returns from innovation.243 Like the factory belching pollution, some inventions would not be worth deploying if inventors had to internalize negative externalities. Second, the patent system distorts incentives even further because it does not symmetrically ignore positive and negative externalities (which, in some grand social calculus, may in some contexts cancel out).244 Rather, it asymmetrically allows inventors to internalize positive but not negative externalities.

As a preliminary matter, one must distinguish this argument from the commonly asserted contention that the patent system should aim to maximize innovative efficiency, leaving distributive considerations to other bodies of law, namely the tax system.245 It is important to emphasize that internalizing externalities itself is important to maximizing efficiency (although, as we shall see, it also has distributive benefits). This Article’s critique sounds in the dominant logic of efficiency; to allocate resources for innovation efficiently, the patent system must account for externalities. Patent law’s externality asymmetry fails to do this, thus introducing three distortions that undermine efficiency.246

a. Patents May Overincentivize Innovation

First, at the broadest level, patents likely overincentivize innovation. A system that allows inventors to capture a significant share of the external benefits of their inventions while bearing no responsibility for their external harms will tend to incentivize innovation beyond the socially optimal level. Put differently, if patentees internalized some of the harms that their inventions imposed on others, there would be less innovation. This could occur in at least two ways. First, if patents effectively facilitated transactions between inventors and individuals harmed by patented technologies, voluntary exchanges would lead to such individuals paying patentees to not deploy those technologies.247 Second, if patentees bore greater accountability for the harms of their technologies on third parties, they would be less likely to invent. For example, if Mark Zuckerberg and other Facebook engineers knew that patenting their “filter bubble” technology would force them to bear some of the costs of ideological polarization, they might have thought twice before developing it.248

This insight offers a new gloss on the economic argument that patents can induce socially wasteful “patent races.” This account contends that patents overincentivize innovation when prevailing firms capture more than a particular fraction of total surplus.249 By providing too great a reward, the patent system can induce too many inventors to chase exclusive rights, thus resulting in wasteful and duplicative effort.250 To this existing account, this Article adds the insight that patents also overincentivize innovation by allowing inventors to ignore negative externalities. Both sides of the coin—increasing rewards and neglecting costs—drive overinvestment in innovation. Due to the one-way incentives provided by patents, society is likely investing too much in innovation to the exclusion of other valuable uses of scarce human, physical, and financial capital.251

b. Patents May Incentivize the Wrong Mix of Innovations

Second, patents may incentivize the wrong mix of innovations. Due to patent law’s externality asymmetry, innovations that create high negative externalities (which patentees can ignore) are likely to be overrepresented relative to their socially optimal level. In a stylized example, assuming that both gas-guzzling internal combustion engines and more fuel-efficient hybrid engines have similar prices and demand curves, the patent system provides equal incentives for inventors to invent both. The fact that gas guzzlers generate significantly greater negative externalities than hybrids is not accounted for in any way by the patent system. This is part and parcel of a larger difficulty in which market prices—particularly in the presence of externalities—do not accurately reflect the social costs and benefits of various resources.252 Therefore, patents not only overincentivize innovation in general, they also distort the allocation of innovative resources toward producing and deploying more technologies generating high negative externalities than would be socially optimal.

c. Patents Provide Suboptimal Incentives for Technological Design

Third, at the most granular level, patent law’s externality asymmetry may provide suboptimal incentives for technological design. For instance, if inventors were more directly accountable for the negative externalities of their technologies, they would design their technologies differently.

Take, for example, patented predictive policing technology. Such technology offers obvious benefits by allowing police departments to better allocate law enforcement resources. As noted, however, inventors hardwired this technology with the “broken windows” theory of policing that may lead to racial profiling and other negative externalities. If patentees were more accountable for the third-party harms of their inventions, they would be more likely to engineer safeguards against such harms. In this case, accounting for such third-party harms might lead the inventors to remove the “broken windows” algorithm from their invention or program automatic prompts to guard users against implicit bias. Attentiveness to negative externalities may lead an inventor to engineer a technology in a way that retains valuable functionality while reducing external costs. However, the present patent regime, which does not hold inventors accountable for negative externalities, does not provide this incentive.253

2. Distributive Concerns

In addition to undermining efficiency, patent law’s externality asymmetry also harms distributive equity. It is probably a fair assumption that the median patentee is wealthier than the median nonpatentee. It is beyond doubt that the median Facebook employee is wealthier than the median U.S. citizen adversely affected by Facebook’s filter bubble technology. A system that allows patentees to internalize positive externalities from their inventions while disregarding negative externalities exacerbates this wealth inequality. Patentees earn innovation-related rents while foisting uncompensated costs on other, less wealthy parties.254

It bears noting that while conventional economic wisdom views distributive concerns as orthogonal to efficiency, that is not always the case. Given the principle of diminishing marginal utility, “pure” wealth transfers from poorer to richer persons not only impair distributive justice, they also reduce overall welfare. After all, the thousandth dollar earned by a low-wage worker contributes more to overall welfare than the five millionth dollar earned by a high-wage innovator.255 And given that social welfare functions are likely to be averse to inequality, innovation that exacerbates inequality also decreases overall welfare.256 This Section discusses the value of distributive equity in and of itself, but it acknowledges that such equity can also enhance efficiency, the lodestar of welfare analysis.

Negative innovation externalities impose uncompensated costs on third parties, thus exacerbating wealth gaps between innovators and affected individuals. This is true of technological externalities, which have real resource effects on external parties.257 Facebook’s filter bubble, which increases the profits of a fabulously wealthy company, depresses the utility functions of ordinary citizens, who must expend more effort to cut through misinformation and maintain civil political discourse. While the patentees of predictive policing systems profit from licensing their technology, their technology imposes costs on marginalized members of society who may be victims of biased algorithms.

The distributive harms of negative innovation externalities are also evident with pecuniary externalities. Recall that pecuniary externalities operate directly through the price system and result in wealth transfers between economic agents.258 While many economists regard pecuniary externalities as irrelevant to overall efficiency, this is not the case; where markets are not competitive or where transactions do not occur, pecuniary externalities can directly harm overall welfare.259 Furthermore, as discussed previously, distributive inequities arising from pecuniary externalities can indirectly diminish welfare through varying marginal utilities of wealth and social utility functions that value equality.260 Moreover, whether or not pecuniary externalities impair efficiency, distributive inequities can be troubling in their own right and justify at least partial internalization of negative externalities.261

Take, for example, autonomous vehicles that threaten the jobs of millions of professional drivers. Economists regard this as a pecuniary rather than technological externality because it operates through the market system by depressing wages.262 Welfare analysis probably suggests that the macroscopic benefits of this technology outweigh its costs, and this Article does not suggest using the patent system or other regulatory levers to suppress this innovation. However, autonomous vehicles do produce troubling negative externalities in the form of regressive wealth redistribution that may warrant intervention. And patent law’s externality asymmetry contributes to these negative externalities. Autonomous vehicles are a subset of AI-based innovations that have attracted significant concern for their ability to intensify wealth inequalities.263 Economists predict that self-driving cars will decrease wages for professional drivers264 and that automation in general may lead to widespread unemployment.265 It bears emphasizing that job losses implicate more than just economic harms given that jobs provide psychological rewards such as meaning, dignity, and fulfillment.266 On the other hand, manufacturers and owners of autonomous vehicles—and the patentees of the underlying technology driving these vehicles—will benefit. These distributive inequities have real social and political salience; Andrew Yang and Elon Musk have cited the potential for automation to displace workers to justify a universal basic income.267 Aside from impairing efficiency, patent law’s externality asymmetry can contribute to troubling distributive effects.

3. Fairness

Finally, patent law’s externality asymmetry also undermines fairness. It does so in at least two ways. First, the very existence of a negative externality compromises fairness because it is a cost imposed on third parties without their consent. Citizens whose electorate is impoverished because of a social media network, hardworking drivers who lose their livelihoods to automation, and individuals unconstitutionally searched by police because of an algorithm can all claim to have been treated unfairly. It is one thing to be harmed by technology when one is aware of and accepts certain risks, such as when a patient takes a drug and experiences uncomfortable but anticipated side effects. It is another thing to be harmed by technology through processes over which one has no control or even input. While much normative analysis focuses on efficiency and, to a lesser extent, distributive concerns, there is a palpable element of unfairness to having to bear the costs of someone else’s actions.

Second, patent law’s externality asymmetry exacerbates this unfairness by allowing patentees to profit from their inventions while not holding them accountable for third-party costs.268 As the term “asymmetry” implies, there is something unbalanced and uneven about a one-way ratchet in which patentees can internalize a meaningful share of the positive externalities of their inventions but do not have to internalize any of their negative externalities. As legal scholar Camilla Hrdy argues in the context of patented automation technology, “[T]he owners of this intellectual property, such as Eli Whitney, NCR Corp., Google, and Uber, profit. But they do not internalize the full costs that those same inventions impose on workers across the economy—workers whose skills are now made obsolete by the advancement of technology.”269 As mentioned, the patent system is both receptive to and constrained by common conceptions of fairness.270 Beyond impairing efficiency and distributive goals, patent law’s externality asymmetry is also troublingly unfair.

V. Policy Prescriptions and Theoretical Implications

This Article has argued that patents asymmetrically internalize positive but not negative externalities associated with technological innovation. While foundational economic theory asserts that patents function similarly to physical property in internalizing externalities, this Article has shown otherwise; physical property rights internalize negative externalities in several ways that do not apply to patents. This Article has further argued that patent law’s externality asymmetry contributes to a variety of social ills by undermining efficiency, distributive equity, and fairness.

The overarching policy implication of this analysis is that there is little reason to think that the patent system achieves a socially efficient mix of innovations. This is an important realization given that defenders of the patent system point to voluntary, property rights–based market exchanges as the paragon of efficiency.271 This presumption of efficiency overlooks a basic economic point: prices do not signal social value—and markets do not allocate resources efficiently—in the presence of externalities. Commentators have explored how the patent system undersupplies innovations that generate significant positive externalities.272 For instance, due to compromised demand signals and the difficulties of capturing positive externalities, markets tend to undersupply “infrastructural” technologies that facilitate wide swaths of downstream productive activities.273 This Article adds the insight that the patent system oversupplies innovations that generate significant negative externalities. Considering both distortions, it is highly doubtful that the patent system (or any market-based system of technological development) gets the socially optimal level of innovation correct.274

Importantly, this critique of the patent system arises within the dominant idiom of economic efficiency. The patent system has attracted criticism on several normative grounds outside the dominant law-and-economics objective of efficiency. In particular, commentators have argued that the patent system should be more attentive to distributive justice and fairness.275 Others have advocated alternate measures of welfare other than the dominant paradigm of preference satisfaction, such as subjective welfare or objective well-being.276 This Article is sympathetic to many of these critiques. Importantly, however, it reveals that the patent system falls short even on its conventional terms. Even within the dominant paradigm of efficiency and welfare maximization (as defined by preference satisfaction), the patent system misallocates resources for innovation by ignoring negative externalities (and many positive ones as well). Thus, even law-and-economics defenders of the patent system should favor correctives to better achieve their goal of innovative efficiency.

This Part turns to the implications of these findings for policy and theory. It advances two related policy changes. First, it proposes a modest requirement that patent applicants disclose reasonably foreseeable social implications of their technologies as a condition of obtaining a patent. Such disclosure would force patentees to consider the potential externalities of their inventions, and it would also generate useful private information for policymakers to craft regulatory responses to emerging technologies. Second and relatedly, this Part argues for greater integration of the patent system and other regulatory frameworks to internalize negative externalities from innovations. A wide array of legal interventions—from environmental regulation to tort liability to tax law—internalize the negative externalities of technologies, patented and otherwise. Policymakers should view these nonpatent mechanisms as essential to achieving the patent system’s goal of efficiently allocating resources of innovation. Furthermore, this Part shows how the patent system can be a valuable source of information to inform and improve such regulatory responses. Finally, this Part explores several broader implications of this Article. In particular, it cautions against undue technological optimism in innovation law and policy, and it adds greater nuance to the widely accepted view that property rights internalize externalities.

A. A Modest Role for the Patent System in Internalizing Negative Externalities

The present inability of the patent system to internalize negative externalities gives rise to an important question: What is the proper role of the patent system in performing this function? This Article argues that it can only play a limited role. This is somewhat ironic given that, by incentivizing investments in innovation, the patent system causes (or at least exacerbates) many of these negative externalities. For a variety of reasons, however, the patent system is ill-suited to directly internalize negative externalities from many patented inventions.

First, the patent system is a blunt instrument that lacks the granularity of other regulatory mechanisms to internalize innovation externalities. The development and application of a technology presents numerous potential opportunities for internalizing negative externalities. Consider, for instance, the invention and deployment of an internal-combustion engine that emits large amounts of greenhouse gases when operated at high capacity. One could internalize the negative externalities of this engine by, for instance, banning it outright,277 discouraging its development by denying its patentability, or regulating or taxing its use by end users. In many cases, innovation externalities depend significantly on how parties use a technology. For instance, perhaps utilizing the engine at less than full capacity greatly reduces emissions, which suggests the appropriateness of some kind of regulation to limit such use. However, the patent system has no ability to regulate how parties use a technology and is a rather blunt instrument for internalizing externalities. At most, the patent system can determine if an invention gets a patent.278 It cannot directly force an inventor to redesign a technology or require that downstream parties only use it in a particular manner. As discussed further below, other legal mechanisms that feature greater granularity play a valuable role in internalizing negative externalities from innovations in a more contextual and use-based manner.279

Additionally, the patent system features several pragmatic and institutional constraints that limit its ability to internalize externalities from patented inventions. First, there are challenges of timing and foreseeability. Many negative externalities from patented inventions are speculative at the time of invention and patent prosecution. Even if inventors or patent examiners could foresee these externalities, they could not precisely predict their scope and magnitude. Second and relatedly, the PTO lacks institutional competence to identify and evaluate negative externalities. PTO examiners are experts in technical fields, but they are not experts in identifying negative externalities from technologies.280 As noted, these same institutional competence limitations contributed to the demise of the moral utility doctrine.281

While this analysis suggests that the patent system should play a modest role in internalizing innovation externalities, it can still make valuable contributions. Some might argue that the patent system should not concern itself with internalizing externalities because other regulatory mechanisms are better situated to do so. This Article does not argue that the patent system should displace these other internalizing mechanisms; rather, it should supplement them. The persistence of significant negative externalities from patented technologies—even those subject to downstream regulation—suggests that existing regulations are inadequate, perhaps due to lack of enforcement or legislative and regulatory capture. Internalizing mechanisms can be additive; for some kinds of inventions, there is good reason to utilize both the patent system and downstream regulations to more fully internalize negative externalities. It may be particularly appropriate to use the patent system to internalize negative externalities where an invention’s negative externalities are intrinsic to its purpose or design and less dependent on how someone uses it. In such cases, denying patentability can significantly discourage the development and dissemination of such inventions (without resorting to outright bans). Indeed, this kind of logic informed the moral utility requirement, which historically denied the patentability of “immoral” inventions such as methods of assassination.282

Finally, as elaborated further below, the patent system can play a valuable role in generating information about emerging and potentially problematic inventions, thus assisting policymakers in crafting appropriate regulations to internalize those inventions’ negative externalities.

Various reforms could enhance the patent system’s capacity to internalize the negative externalities of patented inventions. Focusing on automation technologies, economists Anton Korinek and Joseph Stiglitz argue that shortening the patent term could mitigate the pecuniary externalities of automation by redistributing some innovator surplus to workers and consumers.283 Legal scholar Camilla Hrdy has proposed requiring inventors of automation technologies to disclose the negative effects of their inventions, with the possibility of denying patents on technologies that displace significant numbers of jobs.284

This Article proposes a more general, disclosure-based method to help internalize negative externalities from patented technologies in all fields of innovation. Within this proposal, patent examiners could flag individual patent applications for additional disclosure if they raised significant potential for negative externalities. Patent applicants would then be required to disclose potential harms by including a “Societal Impacts” section in their application. Importantly, this disclosure would operate as a purely procedural requirement. If flagged, patent applicants would have to disclose all reasonably foreseeable harms of their technology, but such disclosures would typically not be the basis for rejecting the application.285 By largely eliminating the threat of denying patentability, this requirement would encourage patent applicants to provide the most candid and thorough disclosure of potential technological harms.

While this proposal faces significant challenges of compliance, it still represents a valuable improvement over the status quo. At the margin, such a disclosure requirement would encourage some patent applicants to sincerely grapple with the consequences of their invention. It is possible, however, that many applicants subject to this “Societal Impacts” requirement would not take it seriously. However, while patent examiners would generally not reject patent applications on substantive grounds due to disclosed externalities, they could reject applications on procedural grounds if they had reason to believe that an applicant had not fully disclosed societal impacts in good faith.286 It is also possible that patent applicants would file long, boilerplate lists of potential adverse impacts akin to risk disclosures submitted by public companies in response to Securities and Exchange Commission requirements. Such mandatory disclosures have been variously criticized as both overreporting and underreporting risks, neither of which is ideal.287 Here again, the patent examiner’s procedural review could prevent patent applicants from simply filing long lists of generic risks that are both overinclusive and insufficiently tailored to the particular invention at issue. Over time, a kind of “prior art” of model Societal Impacts statements would emerge, thus making it easier for patent applicants and examiners to recognize effective disclosures.

This decidedly modest proposal would help internalize negative externalities in two ways.288 First, it would be a consideration-forcing mechanism that would compel inventors to identify, contemplate, and evaluate the potential harms and social implications of their inventions. Almost by definition, parties do not account for externalities when pursuing a course of action. Of course, inventors may be aware of the negative externalities of their technologies and do nothing to mitigate them. However, for some inventors, awareness of harmful third-party effects may spur behavioral change. In rare cases, such awareness may lead an inventor to abandon an invention. More likely, however, it may motivate inventors to redesign their inventions to reduce negative externalities. As in the example above, forcing inventors to consider the negative implications of predictive policing may lead them to engineer certain safeguards against biased algorithms.289

Additionally, this proposal would help fill the gaps left by existing downstream regulations that already internalize negative externalities from technology. Inventors undoubtedly consider some downstream regulations—such as environmental laws and tort liability—when designing new technologies. However, some negative externalities—such as increased political polarization from Facebook’s filter bubble—do not fit comfortably within existing regulations or causes of action. A requirement for patentees to consider the broad social implications of their inventions would encourage them to confront a wider set of negative externalities that downstream regulations do not currently address.

Notably, this proposal dovetails with actual and proposed practice in other areas of scientific research that conditions certain rewards on disclosing the social implications of one’s research. For decades, the National Science Foundation has evaluated funding proposals on two criteria: intellectual merit and “broader impacts,” which considers whether and how a project helps achieve wider societal goals.290 Additionally, scientists have suggested that peer reviewers consider the social implications of research when determining whether to recommend article manuscripts for publication.291

Second, and perhaps more importantly, this proposal would be an information-forcing mechanism that would generate information about patented inventions from particularly knowledgeable sources—inventors themselves. In so doing, this proposal would sidestep institutional competence limitations of patent examiners, who are not experts in identifying the third-party costs of new technologies. As elaborated further below, such private information about social media, autonomous vehicles, big data, and other innovations would be highly valuable to policymakers when crafting interventions to address problematic technologies or uses of technology.292

B. Integrating the Patent System with Other Regulatory Mechanisms to Internalize Negative Externalities

Given the modest nature of this proposal, the broader prescription arising from this Article is greater integration of patent and nonpatent mechanisms in a holistic policy framework to internalize negative externalities from technological innovation.

In recent years, scholars have fruitfully explored the importance of nonpatent policy levers in supplementing the patent system and promoting innovation. For instance, government grants, tax breaks, and prizes fill sizable gaps in the patent system in generating and distributing new technologies.293 Notably, these are “affirmative” mechanisms that encourage innovative activity. In the language of externalities, they are subsidies aimed at helping innovators internalize more of the positive externalities of their creations.

This Article explores the flip side of this dynamic by highlighting the significant negative externalities of patented technologies and the need to internalize them. This Article has further shown that the patent system is limited in its ability to internalize negative externalities. However, many other areas of law operate as “restrictive” mechanisms that internalize negative externalities from technology—patented or otherwise. In so doing, these mechanisms help fill significant gaps in the patent system; indeed, “downstream” regulation is generally superior to the patent system in internalizing externalities because it is more granular in nature and can regulate particular uses of technologies. For instance, environmental laws regulate greenhouse gas emissions,294 pesticides,295 and toxic substances.296 The Food and Drug Administration regulates drugs, and it may require drug manufacturers to develop Risk Evaluation and Mitigation Strategies for particularly risky drugs.297 Tort law—particularly products liability law—can internalize negative externalities from poorly designed technologies.298 Congress has been debating numerous proposals to modify Section 230 of the Communications Decency Act to impose greater liability on social media companies for content posted on their platforms.299 A primary legal mechanism for internalizing externalities is Pigouvian taxation.300 For instance, a carbon tax would help internalize negative externalities from all carbon-emitting technologies (including patented inventions).301 Commentators have also proposed taxing owners of patents on automation technology and redistributing gains to displaced workers.302 Local jurisdictions can also act; for example, San Francisco has prohibited the police and other government agencies from using facial recognition technology.303

This Article calls for greater integration of patent and nonpatent mechanisms to internalize negative externalities from innovation. Such integration should occur on both conceptual and pragmatic levels. At a conceptual level, policymakers should recognize that “restrictive” laws and regulations that internalize negative externalities from innovation are not wholly external to the patent system’s objectives. While such restrictive mechanisms appear unhelpful or even antagonistic to the patent system’s aim of promoting technological progress, this Article argues that they are essential for the patent system to achieve its objectives.304 Patent law does not aim to maximize innovation at all costs; it seeks efficiency in the allocation of resources for innovation. Patents, however, are unlikely to achieve this goal because they asymmetrically internalize positive but not negative innovation externalities. In essence, patents provide too much acceleration and not enough braking. Restrictive mechanisms outside of patent law can correct for patent law’s externality asymmetry and help achieve more efficient outcomes. In this sense, environmental law, food and drug regulation, tort law, communications law, taxes, and other regulatory mechanisms are not external to the patent system but play a critical role in achieving its goals.

Scholars recognize that “affirmative” mechanisms such as public funding, tax incentives, and prizes both complement and support the patent system’s aims. In symmetric fashion, “restrictive” mechanisms that internalize externalities from innovation also support the patent system’s aim of efficiently allocating resources for innovation.

At a pragmatic level, this Article also argues for strengthening connections between the patent system and other forms of technological regulation, primarily by providing valuable information. Many technologies generating significant negative externalities in society today, from filter bubbles to autonomous vehicles to predictive policing, began as patented inventions. While the patent system is not well equipped to internalize the negative externalities of such inventions directly, it is uniquely positioned to generate information about them. In the classic formulation of the patent quid pro quo, inventors receive valuable exclusive rights in exchange for disclosing the technical details of a novel invention.305 The inducement of exclusive rights, however, can motivate even more disclosure, for instance into the foreseeable social ramifications of a new technology.306 Such privately generated information is highly valuable in alerting policymakers to impending problems from emerging technologies and helping them craft appropriate responses utilizing environmental law, food and drug regulation, tax law, or any number of other regulatory levers.307 Such information can allow the patent system, which is not well positioned to internalize negative externalities directly, to support downstream regulations that can internalize externalities in a nuanced and contextual manner.

It bears emphasizing that not all negative externalities warrant internalization, and policymakers must decide when efficiency, distributive equity, fairness, or other considerations justify intervention.308 Furthermore, internalization is a dynamic rather than static analysis. As Brett Frischmann reminds us, “[T]he benefits and costs of internalization must include not only impacts on internalizing actors but also impacts on third parties.”309 Thus, for instance, internalizing a negative externality for one party could generate a cascade of difficult-to-predict positive or negative externalities for others. Given the complexity of these interdependencies, policymakers can make better decisions regarding whether and how to internalize innovation externalities when they rely on better information.

C. Broader Implications: Technological Realism and the Limits of Property Rights

At a broader level, this Article argues for greater technological realism in innovation law and policy. From individual technologies that enhance our daily lives to macroscopic contributions to economic growth, the benefits of innovation are undeniable. Technological optimism clearly informs the patent system, which exists to promote technological progress. Such optimism also informs patent policy and scholarship; while patent scholars debate whether patents are good or bad in particular situations, the unstated assumption is that technology itself is good and, all things being equal, more technology is better.310 However, technology creates costs as well as benefits. More technology does not always advance social welfare, especially when that technology creates negative externalities. Greater technological realism—a measured accounting of the costs and benefits of technology—will lead to more enlightened innovation policy.

This Article ends by considering the implications of patents and cutting-edge technologies for foundational property theory. Demsetz famously argued that property rights internalize externalities. Furthermore, he generalized beyond the land context to argue that property rights serve this function in numerous settings, including intellectual property.311 As this Article has shown, however, the precise subject matter, context, and design of property rights are crucial to their ability to internalize externalities. In the land context, property rights cover rivalrous assets, facilitate negotiations between a relatively small number of parties, and create affirmative duties to not harm others. These parameters are very different for patents, which internalize positive externalities but do little to internalize negative ones. In sum, this Article questions the foundational belief that granting exclusive rights, in and of itself, will substantially internalize externalities. And where property rights and private ordering do not perform this function, public intervention can play a valuable role in advancing efficiency and other normative objectives.

Conclusion

Technology generates significant positive externalities, a dynamic reflected in the very existence of the patent system itself. This Article has called attention to the less appreciated fact that technology also generates significant negative externalities. Foundational economic theory suggests that internalizing positive and negative externalities is important for achieving efficient resource allocation. This Article has argued that patent law exhibits a striking asymmetry in this regard: while patents exist to internalize positive externalities, they do very little to internalize negative externalities associated with innovation. Patent law’s externality asymmetry is particularly notable in light of influential theory positing that property rights are critical to internalizing both kinds of externalities. In the land context, property rights mitigate negative externalities in several ways that are largely inapplicable to patents. Patents do not resolve tragedies of the commons, and they encourage rapid exploitation of technologies rather than measured considerations of their third-party harms. Patents do not realistically facilitate efficiency-maximizing negotiations between technology owners and parties harmed by their technologies. Finally, patents create no duties for patentees to mitigate (or even consider) the harms of their technologies on external parties. Patents are a one-way ratchet that allows patentees to profit from their inventions while not holding them accountable for their third-party costs.

Patent law’s externality asymmetry is problematic for several reasons. Most prominently, it undermines patent law’s primary aim of efficiency. By ignoring negative externalities, the patent system overincentivizes innovation, incentivizes the wrong mix of innovations, and provides suboptimal incentives for technological design. Beyond diminishing efficiency, patent law’s externality asymmetry also undermines distributive equity and fairness. While the patent system’s ability to internalize negative externalities is limited, this Article proposes compelling patent applicants to disclose the potential harms of certain technologies as a condition of obtaining a patent. This is a decidedly modest proposal, and this Article also highlights the need to integrate patent and nonpatent regulatory mechanisms to internalize the negative externalities of technologies—patented and otherwise. It calls for greater technological realism in innovation law and policy, and it questions the fundamental association of property rights and market exchanges with efficient allocations of resources. Market allocations are not always efficient (particularly in the presence of externalities), and while technology offers significant promise, it also creates significant perils.

 


* Martin Luther King Jr. Professor of Law, UC Davis School of Law. I would like to thank Dennis Crouch, Brett Frischmann, Al Lin, Michael Meurer, Jason Rantanen, Josh Sarnoff, and workshop participants at UC Davis School of Law, the University of Iowa College of Law, and Boston University School of Law for valuable comments on earlier versions of this Article. Thanks to Dean Kevin Johnson and Senior Associate Dean Afra Afsharipour for providing generous institutional support for this project. This research was supported by a grant from the UC Davis Academic Senate Committee on Research. I am grateful to Aoife Devereux, Katie Weeks, and the UC Davis School of Law library staff for excellent research assistance. Finally, I would like to thank the outstanding editors of Cardozo Law Review.