Introduction
“Courts of justice are universally acknowledged to be vested, by their very creation, with power to impose silence, respect, and decorum, in their presence, and submission to their lawful mandates.” These powers are “governed not by rule or statute but by the control necessarily vested in courts to manage their own affairs so as to achieve the orderly and expeditious disposition of cases.”1
This principle, repeatedly declared by the United States Supreme Court since 1812, is a fundamental tenet of federal courts jurisprudence.2 The existence of such powers is described as being virtually self-evident. Inherent powers are those “necessary to the exercise of all others”3 and are said to derive from the “control necessarily vested in courts to manage their own affairs.”4
Yet when courts seek to apply these necessary and self-evident powers to specific legal problems, their precise nature and scope turn out to be surprisingly mysterious. The inherent powers doctrine has been called the “murkiest, and most extensive” of the federal courts’ sanctioning powers.5 One civil procedure scholar describes it as a “pretty ill-defined” doctrine that has been used to justify a wide variety of judicial actions.6 He notes that it “gets hauled out of the attic at unpredictable times to deal with odd-ball cases.”7 Another scholar states that the Supreme Court “has offered remarkably different interpretations of congressional authority over the judiciary’s inherent powers, occasionally in the same opinion.”8 A third complains, “The Supreme Court’s jurisprudence is schizophrenic: it sometimes states that inherent powers are available only when they are indispensable to the discharge of the judicial power, yet it often authorizes their use in less pressing situations.”9
All these disparaging descriptions are, to a considerable degree, accurate. The scope of inherent judicial authority is frustratingly vague and its use in particular cases is frequently unpredictable. Moreover, the very source of the doctrine remains unclear. Is it grounded on constitutional principle, specifically the grant of judicial power in Article III of the Constitution, or is it simply a manifestation of the judiciary’s traditional power to manage its own practices and procedures? Despite two hundred years of Supreme Court decisions invoking, describing, and applying the doctrine, it remains vague, ambiguous, and, yes, deeply schizophrenic.
Much recent scholarship has sought to remove that ambiguity with prescriptive solutions to make the doctrine more consistent and more normatively defensible.10 This Article has a different goal. It views inherent judicial authority,11 with all its contradictions, as an important concept central to the functioning of the federal courts. The ambiguity of that doctrine is not a bug but a feature, one that has been recognized, preserved, and even implicitly approved by decisions of the United States Supreme Court. If such a doctrine remains confusing and contradictory, there are probably good institutional reasons for that. This Article seeks to explore and understand those reasons.12
One must begin by recognizing that inherent judicial authority is confusing because it encompasses two quite different concepts of judicial power derived from two different sources. First there is the judicial power conferred by Article III of the Constitution.13 This includes both the core express constitutional power to adjudicate cases and controversies, and the related constitutionally based inherent powers that are essential to the proper functioning of a court and that federal judges have by virtue of their status as Article III judges.14 The most frequently cited examples are a court’s power to maintain respect and decorum and enforce its orders through sanctions such as contempt, as well as a court’s power to determine its own practices and procedures.15 Yet there are many other instances in which courts invoke inherent judicial authority in a rather different sense to authorize discretionary judicial conduct regarding procedural matters where such action is not expressly authorized by any statute or rule. These do not refer to a constitutional power. Rather they invoke an inherent right to exercise interstitial decision-making authority over judicial processes in the absence of other controlling statutes or rules. Such power has been invoked to justify a wide variety of nonstatutory procedural innovations, from appointment of special masters to dismissal for forum non conveniens.16 The sources of this power are most readily understood and justified, in contemporary terms, as applications of federal procedural common law.17
In order to understand the role that ambiguity plays in the Supreme Court’s doctrine of inherent judicial power it is necessary to recognize three central facts. First, in the two hundred years since the Supreme Court first recognized the doctrine, the Court has never invalidated any federal statute on the ground that it unconstitutionally infringed the implied inherent judicial powers of the federal courts.18 Second, during that same period, the Supreme Court affirmed a broad range of nonconstitutional powers in the federal district courts recognizing substantial judicial freedom to innovate in procedural matters, even where such innovation might be seen as inconsistent with applicable federal statutes and rules. Third, the Supreme Court’s description of the doctrine of inherent judicial authority in these cases has been confusing and contradictory.19 It has tended to treat all inherent judicial authority as a single continuum of power, while implying that some forms of inherent judicial power may be constitutionally required while others clearly are not.20
These three facts about the inherent-judicial-authority puzzle are closely related. Indeed, the third, the confused mashing of constitutional and nonconstitutional powers into a single continuum, largely explains and is responsible for the other two. By treating exercises of procedural common law decision-making as part of a continuum with implied constitutional inherent power, the Court can avoid deciding many difficult constitutional questions. By ambiguously justifying an exercise of district court power as “necessary” to the proper functioning of that court, the Supreme Court can avoid the need to state whether such necessity is created by constitutional separation-of-powers concerns or merely by Congress’s failure to act. Conversely, if the issue is one in which a federal statute does seem to impinge on what might be a constitutional power of the judiciary, the effect of the statute can frequently be limited by reinterpretation so that it is seen as a mere regulation of the application of that power. Such regulations, if they do not abrogate the inherent judicial power itself, are mere applications of federal procedural common law. They are subject to congressional control and are not seen to raise serious constitutional issues.
Describing these common law procedural rulings as exercises of inherent judicial authority “necessary” to the proper functioning of the courts gives them added rhetorical dignity. The ambiguous but correct assertion that courts have broad power to exercise discretion and innovate procedurally whenever “necessary” for the proper functioning of the courts does not only justify the broad scope of procedural common law decision-making power asserted by the Court. It also validates interpretative strategies that the Supreme Court has used to permit judicial procedural innovation even where it is arguably constrained by federal statutes or rules.
The Supreme Court Justices are the ultimate arbiters of the constitutional separation of powers. They define the boundaries of the powers conferred on each of the three branches of government. However, those same Justices are also heads of the judicial branch with ultimate responsibility for the proper and efficient functioning of the federal courts. While this does not create a formal conflict of interest, it certainly creates tension between the Court’s desire to act and be seen as a neutral and independent adjudicator of constitutional issues, and its presumed desire to also protect and preserve the ability of federal judges to function effectively and without undue interference from other governmental entities. This means that decision-making regarding controversial separation-of-powers issues will reflect practical political as well as legal considerations.21 The doctrine of inherent judicial authority, with all its confusing and contradictory aspects, plays an important role in mitigating these tensions. The complex institutional role of the Court, which seeks to avoid constitutional confrontation with the other branches while also protecting federal judicial independence and effectiveness, helps explain the unique and otherwise puzzling aspects of the doctrine.
This Article seeks to illustrate, understand, and to some extent justify the ambiguity in the prevailing doctrine of inherent judicial authority. The first Part introduces the theoretical framework for both the constitutional and common law–based conceptions of inherent judicial authority and examines their confusing conflation in actual case law. It does this primarily through an extended consideration of two rather different Supreme Court cases, both of which purport to apply the doctrine. It illustrates how the Court uses ambiguity to elide constitutional questions and enhance the protection of nonconstitutional judicial power. The next two Parts trace the development of the doctrine over time. Part II shows how the federal judicial power was left mostly undefined by the drafters of the Constitution, largely for prudential and political reasons. Fears of an expanded federal judicial power, unresponsive to local concerns, were a major argument of those who opposed the Constitution’s ratification.22 For similar reasons, the first Congress, in passing the legislation creating the lower federal courts, also included provisions designed to cabin their powers within the traditional limits of common law courts, again leaving those powers largely undefined.23 Accordingly, the doctrine of inherent judicial authority has been developed largely through Supreme Court case law. Part III traces that development over the last two hundred years. It focuses particularly on inherent judicial power to sanction litigation misconduct and to develop practices and procedures for the courts not authorized by statute or rule.24 By closely analyzing the rulings and arguments of the Justices in specific cases, we can see how the doctrine has developed, how it reflects the political concerns of different eras, and how the Court’s conflation of the multitier conception of inherent authority into a single continuum of power has played an important role in promoting judicial independence and flexibility.
In the final Part, this enhanced understanding of inherent judicial authority is applied to an important current legal issue, the scope and validity of Federal Rule of Civil Procedure 37(e)(2), which prohibits a federal court from ordering severe sanctions for loss of electronically stored information (ESI) unless it can be shown that the spoliator “acted with the intent to deprive another party of the information’s use in the litigation.”25 This Rule is of great interest and importance to practicing litigators,26 and concerns have been raised both regarding its validity and the extent to which it may restrict inherent judicial authority to sanction litigation misconduct. Utilizing the novel understanding of the doctrine set forth in this Article, I explain why Rule 37(e)(2) is likely to be interpreted narrowly to maintain substantial judicial discretion over sanctioning authority and the interpretive strategies judges are likely to use to retain flexibility to sanction misconduct regarding ESI preservation while avoiding a direct constitutional challenge to the Rule’s validity.
I. A Tale of Two Cases (of Inherent Judicial Authority)
We begin with two Supreme Court decisions that illustrate the complexity and ambiguity of inherent judicial authority. One is a clear example of procedural common law decision-making. The other involves powers close to those the Court has described as constitutionally required and essential to the role of the judge. Yet in both cases the Court’s decisions conflate these two types of decision-making, treating them as a single continuum of judicial power. Together, they illustrate some of the ways that doctrinal ambiguity helps the Court preserve and expand the discretionary procedural authority of the district courts while avoiding difficult constitutional issues.
Dietz v. Bouldin27579 U.S. 40 (2016). involved a negligence claim arising from an automobile accident. By the time the case went to trial, the only issue for the jury was whether to award damages in excess of a stipulated amount.28 The jury found for the plaintiff but awarded zero dollars in damages.29 The judge did not immediately realize this was a legally impermissible verdict and dismissed the jury. A few minutes later, the judge ordered the jurors recalled over the objection of defendant’s counsel. After a subsequent jury instruction, the jury returned a verdict of fifteen thousand dollars.30 The issue was whether the district judge had the “inherent power to rescind a jury discharge order and recall a jury for further deliberations after identifying an error in the jury’s verdict.”31 Justice Sotomayor, in an opinion joined by six other Justices, held that the action of the district court was a valid exercise of inherent judicial power.32
The judicial power asserted in Dietz was clearly not constitutionally based or essential to the functioning of the court. It was an innovative procedural step taken by the judge without any authorization in existing federal statutes or rules. Nonetheless, it was upheld as a valid exercise of inherent judicial authority even though it was contrary to traditional judicial practice at common law, was arguably inconsistent with Federal Rule of Civil Procedure 51(b), and raised serious constitutional concerns regarding the maintenance of juror impartiality. It was also not in any sense “necessary” for proper functioning of the court. The district judge could have corrected the jury’s erroneous verdict in a traditional but more costly and time-consuming manner by ordering a new trial.
Justice Sotomayor begins her legal discussion by quoting precedential language that “a district court possesses inherent powers that are ‘governed not by rule or statute but by the control necessarily vested in courts to manage their own affairs so as to achieve the orderly and expeditious disposition of cases.’”33 The embedded quotation is from Link v. Wabash Railroad Co.,34 which held that district courts have inherent power, notwithstanding the arguably contrary language of Federal Rule of Civil Procedure 41(b), to dismiss cases for want of prosecution sua sponte. As a precedent for reading federal rules narrowly to preserve a broad scope of procedural discretion for district judges, it is a very appropriate citation. As a statement of the doctrine of inherent judicial authority, it is quite ambiguous. Justice Sotomayor affirms that the doctrine is founded on necessity. Judges must have these powers to do their jobs. But she conflates two different senses of necessity. One sense refers to powers that district judges need to perform their core judicial functions at all. The other refers to powers that district judges need to manage their cases in an optimal manner in the absence of guidance from statutes or rules.35
The inherent judicial authority asserted in Dietz was not constitutionally based. However, by failing clearly to distinguish constitutional from nonconstitutional inherent judicial authority, Justice Sotomayor was able to present the district court’s questionable procedural innovation as part of a well-established continuum of judicial decision-making power that is presumptively valid in the absence of strong countervailing considerations. The inherent power Justice Sotomayor describes is a right to judicial procedural innovation, unauthorized by any statute or rule but potentially justified by considerations of efficiency, convenience, and cost reduction. The power potentially extends to any actions taken by district courts “to manage their dockets and courtrooms with a view toward the efficient and expedient resolution of cases.”36 She describes the powers conferred on district courts by the doctrine as powerful and “poten[t]” and notes that there are only a few limitations on the exercise of such powers, primarily that the actions be “reasonable”37 and not “contrary to any express grant of or limitation on the district court’s power contained in a rule or statute.”38
Dietz was not an easy win for the appellee. There were serious arguments for reversing the actions of the district court, including contrary precedent,39 potential conflicts with federal rules,40 and serious potential to compromise juror impartiality.41 Yet Justice Sotomayor argued that the “potency” of inherent judicial authority, reflecting the need for district judges to manage their courtroom practices efficiently, was strong enough to overcome these serious counterarguments. The language she quotes to demonstrate that potency was from Chambers v. NASCO, Inc.,42 a case involving powers much closer to the court’s core constitutional functions.43
Justice Sotomayor was well aware that the “potent” power recognized in Dietz was not constitutionally based.44 She implies it is close even to the “outer boundaries” of the district court’s procedural common law authority.45 Yet by describing it as part of a broad continuum of judicial powers, some constitutionally based and all justified by a somewhat ambiguous appeal to “necessity,”46 she is able to present it, by virtue of it being part of the district court’s inherent authority, as an important judicial prerogative, one that should not lightly be set aside by countervailing considerations. In this way, a not unreasonable procedural innovation becomes rhetorically associated with and justified by the fundamental powers and structure of the judicial branch. The Court is able to preserve a broad power of judicial procedural freedom while still acknowledging theoretical legislative supremacy.
Unlike Dietz, Chambers v. NASCO, Inc.47501 U.S. 32. is a landmark case, one of the most important inherent authority decisions of the last fifty years. It upholds a broad judicial power to award attorney’s fees for all forms of bad faith litigation misconduct in civil actions, whether or not such conduct is also subject to sanctions under more specific statutes and rules.48 If Dietz was a case near the “outer boundaries” of procedural common law, NASCO was located much closer to the realm of essential constitutional powers. The inherent judicial power to sanction litigation misconduct, which it recognizes, not only supplements but, in appropriate cases, can actually displace more limited rights under the Federal Rules. The opinions in the case strongly imply but never quite state that the right is grounded in constitutionally based inherent judicial power.
NASCO was a suit for specific performance of a contract for the sale of a television station in Lake Charles, Louisiana.49 After the contract was signed but before the closing, the seller changed his mind.50 He refused to file various papers necessary to consummate the sale, which led to the lawsuit.51 Defendant then engaged in a complex series of actions designed to prevent performance of the contract as well as divest the court of its ability to enforce it.52 After determining that neither Federal Rule of Civil Procedure 11 nor 28 U.S.C. § 1927 provided a sufficient basis for sanctioning all the misconduct involved in the case, the district court, relying on its inherent judicial authority, imposed sanctions on defendant Chambers of $996,644.65, the entire amount of NASCO’s litigation costs.53
Justice White, writing the majority opinion, stated that the issue was “whether the District Court, sitting in diversity, properly invoked its inherent power in assessing as a sanction for a party’s bad-faith conduct attorney’s fees and related expenses paid by the party’s opponent to its attorneys.”54 The appellant had argued that the passage of 28 U.S.C. § 1927 and various federal rules “reflect a legislative intent to displace the inherent power,” and that the only sanctions permitted were those authorized under those specific statutes and rules.55
Justice White’s opinion not only argues that the federal district courts’ inherent power to sanction bad faith litigation misconduct with an award of attorney’s fees had not been displaced by legislative action, but it strongly suggests that it cannot constitutionally be so abrogated.56 He begins by citing a string of earlier Supreme Court precedents that describe inherent judicial powers as those courts possess “necessarily” and that courts have “by their very creation,” strongly implying that such powers are constitutionally based.57 Most involve the power to sanction litigation misconduct.58
Yet while there were many precedents that stated, at least in dicta, that judicial power to sanction egregious litigation misconduct was essential and constitutionally based, Justice White was reluctant to hold that the power to award attorney’s fees as a sanction was constitutionally protected. His concern seemed based on the unique status of the “American Rule” against fee shifting and his own prior decision in Alyeska Pipeline Service Co. v. Wilderness Society.59 While that case had recognized three “judicially fashioned exceptions” to the rule, including one for “bad faith” misconduct,60 Justice White had stated that those exceptions were “unquestionably assertions of inherent power in the courts to allow attorneys’ fees in particular situations, unless forbidden by Congress.”61 Having previously characterized this power as a defeasible exercise of procedural common law, not an inherent constitutional power, Justice White was unwilling to repudiate that position. He also expressly declined the opportunity to clearly distinguish between constitutionally based and nonconstitutionally based inherent powers, stating that “this Court has never so classified the inherent powers, and we have no need to do so now.”62
Justice White felt he had no need to make such a distinction, because he held that the inherent power to sanction bad faith litigation misconduct through fee shifting had not been displaced by Rule 11 or any other federal rules or legislation.63 Accordingly, exercise of such inherent power would exist on either constitutional or nonconstitutional grounds.64 The Court does discuss, however, in somewhat theoretical terms, what would happen if there was a conflict between the sanctions available under the Federal Rules and under inherent judicial authority. Justice White states:
[W]hen there is bad-faith conduct in the course of litigation that could be adequately sanctioned under the Rules, the court ordinarily should rely on the Rules rather than the inherent power. But if in the informed discretion of the court, neither the statute nor the Rules are up to the task, the court may safely rely on its inherent power.65
While technically dicta, this also sounds like an instruction to district courts in future cases. It is not an interpretive principle but an allocation of decision-making authority. If a district judge concludes that the sanctions permitted or mandated under the rule are not “up to the task” of adequately sanctioning bad faith litigation misconduct, the inherent power to apply other sanctions, far from being displaced by the conflicting rule, remains available to the district court to use if it deems necessary. It is hard to see this as anything other than an affirmation of the constitutional right of federal judges to sanction bad faith litigation misconduct irrespective of any contrary federal rules or legislation.66
Why does the Court not clearly state whether the inherent judicial power being asserted in NASCO is based on constitutional power or procedural common law? While such a statement might not be necessary to decide the case, it would certainly clarify the law and be of great interest to lawyers and legal scholars. To some degree, the Court’s reluctance reflects traditional avoidance of unnecessary constitutional issues. Yet the constitutional issue here is very close to the surface. Justice White prudently asserts that judges should use legislated sanctioning rules and statutes whenever they are “up to the task” while implicitly affirming the existence of additional judicial powers to act outside their authorization. Yet he never explains the precise source or basis of those additional powers. By asserting constitutional authority in this ambiguous way, the Court gets some distinct benefits. It asserts the power of the federal courts to act, in appropriate cases, contrary to expressly legislated rules, yet does so in a way that does not directly challenge any existing statute or rule. Moreover, it enhances a general awareness among both judges and legislators that the judiciary has an independent sanctioning power that should not be restricted too tightly by rule or statute, lest they be deemed not “up to the task.”
Together, these two cases illustrate the prevalence and usefulness of ambiguity in current Supreme Court jurisprudence regarding inherent judicial authority. By presenting it as a single source of judicial power, authorized in part by fundamental constitutional principle and in part by traditional judicial decision-making, all encapsulated under the ambiguous term “necessity,” the Court reasserts and strengthens the existence of a broad and “potent” power of district courts to innovate procedurally while avoiding the need expressly to claim a constitutional source for such power.
In demonstrating the useful role that ambiguity plays in the Court’s treatment of inherent judicial authority, I do not mean to imply that such ambiguity is the result of a conscious judicial strategy. Rather, as we shall see in the following Sections, it was more likely the result of a series of contingent historical events: the failure of the drafters of the Constitution to specify the powers of the judiciary; early political disputes over the appropriate laws and procedures to be applied in the federal courts; and a tendency of the Supreme Court, in response to that ongoing political and legal uncertainty, to make broad claims about the essential and necessary nature of judicial power in dicta, while actually applying such powers in a far more careful and limited way in accordance with legislative mandates. The result was a conceptual mashup of constitutional– and common law–based inherent powers which, while somewhat confusing and contradictory, have proven useful in avoiding confrontation with the political branches while leaving federal judges free to interpret procedural statutes and rules broadly and innovate when they deem it “necessary.”
II. Judicial Power and Politics in the Early Republic
A. Ambiguity at the Founding
The concept of inherent judicial authority long predates the United States Constitution.67 Early English courts possessed significant authority to conduct their own affairs without express legislation or authorization from the sovereign. This included the power to punish various forms of disruptive conduct as contempt, to prescribe their own rules of practice and procedure, and to dismiss vexatious or frivolous litigation.68 Although the concept of inherent judicial power was familiar in 1787, the drafting of the Constitution and the debates over ratification raised questions as to the scope and nature of the powers to be exercised by the still somewhat hypothetical federal courts.69 The Constitution, with its checks and balances and implicit but far from complete separation of powers, also raised new questions concerning the source of federal inherent judicial authority and the extent to which such authority could be altered or abrogated by Congress.70
The Constitution vested “[t]he judicial Power of the United States” in “one supreme Court, and in such inferior Courts as the Congress may from time to time ordain and establish.”71 The term “judicial power” is not defined,72 and there is little in the records of the Constitutional Convention that sheds light on its precise meaning.73
Section 3 of that Article set forth a series of “cases” (similar to those now listed in Section 2 of Article III) to which “[t]he Jurisdiction of the Supreme Court shall extend.” Id. at 186. The last sentence in that Section stated that “[t]he Legislature may assign any part of the jurisdiction above mentioned (except the trial of the President of the United States) in the manner, and under the limitations which it shall think proper, to such Inferior Courts, as it shall constitute from time to time.” Id. at 186–87. On August 27, 1787, that sentence was deleted by a unanimous vote. Journal, Monday, August 27, 1787, in 2 The Records of the Federal Convention of 1787, supra note 73, at 422, 425. The Convention also unanimously voted to change “The jurisdiction of the Supreme Court” to “The Judicial Power.” Id. A motion to add the sentence “In all the other cases before mentioned the judicial power shall be exercised in such manner as the Legislature shall direct” was defeated six to two. Id.
From these facts one might conclude that “judicial power” was seen as almost synonymous with the concept of jurisdiction, or perhaps a slightly broader “power of judging.” There also appears to have been some reluctance to specify too precisely the degree of control that Congress could exercise over the judicial branch. See infra notes 83–105 and accompanying text. The concept of a separate and independent “judicial power” of government, however, had its roots in a specific concept of separation of powers that can be traced to Montesquieu and Blackstone and that underlies much of the constitutional language.74 It was Montesquieu who first emphasized the importance of an independent judicial power, which he referred to as “la puissance de juger,” the power of judging.75 This concept was adopted and enlarged by Blackstone as the “judicial power.” Blackstone further affirmed the “necessity for an independent judicial power.”76 The express recognition of the judiciary as a separate department of government was a feature of many state constitutions at the time of the Founding.77
The federal judiciary envisioned in the Constitution is far from completely independent. It is subject to substantial legislative and executive control over its personnel, structure, and adjudicative authority. Article III grants to Congress the power to “ordain and establish” inferior federal courts.78
A similar congressional power was recognized in Article I, which gives the legislature power to take other unspecified actions “necessary and proper for carrying into Execution the foregoing Powers.” U.S. Const. art. I, § 8, cl. 18. See James E. Pfander, Article I Tribunals, Article III Courts, and the Judicial Power of The United States, 118 Harv. L. Rev. 643, 673–75 (2004) for a defense of congressional power to create Article I courts based on the difference in the language of the two provisions. Congress is also expressly given power to make “regulations” and “exceptions” to the Supreme Court’s appellate jurisdiction.79 The primary power given to the executive over the judicial branch is the power to appoint federal judges with the advice and consent of the Senate, but not the power to fire them.80
Scholars have noted the relative absence of details in the Constitution’s provisions regarding the federal judiciary.81 There is ambiguity built into the constitutional structure itself, notably between the concept of judicial independence that underlies Article III’s grant of judicial power to the federal courts, and the extensive control the Constitution grants to the other branches over the courts’ jurisdiction, structure, and staffing. This ambiguity and lack of detail have historically created substantial uncertainty with respect to some key questions in Article III jurisprudence. To what extent does Congress have plenary power over creation and jurisdiction of inferior federal courts, as well as Supreme Court appellate jurisdiction, and to what extent is such congressional power limited by Article III and separation-of-powers principles? This issue has been debated almost since the Founding by many prominent constitutional scholars. The issue not only remains unresolved but continues to reflect fundamental disagreements regarding issues of constitutional structure and power.82
An important related issue is how much power Congress has under the Constitution to regulate the judicial process itself. To what extent can it abrogate or alter judicial powers traditionally exercised and justified under the rubric of inherent judicial authority? Here, although there is still disagreement among scholars, a partial consensus has emerged that recognizes that congressional control over the powers of the federal judiciary is substantial but not unlimited, and that federal courts’ inherent judicial authority derives from two separate sources: Article III and common law decision-making authority. It also recognizes that Supreme Court decisions fail to distinguish clearly between these two sources.83
It seems likely that the Constitution’s ambiguity and lack of detail regarding judicial power and the degree of congressional control over the courts were intentional. In 1787, the concept of an independent federal judiciary was itself highly controversial. Many people, even those who favored a stronger federal government, saw no need for federal courts and feared the effect such courts might have on existing legal rights.84 At the most concrete and substantive level, there was concern that the power of local courts to safeguard existing property rights would be impaired and that federal courts would tend to favor creditor banks and merchants over farmer-debtors.85 There was also concern about the procedures that might be followed in federal courts, particularly whether federal courts, under their equitable authority, could curtail existing rights to jury trials.86 More broadly, there was a recognition that the courts that had developed in the various states were quite different from those in England. American judges had less legal training and relied less on formal legal rules (often because authoritative legal materials were unavailable) and relied more on concepts of fairness and justice that reflected local conditions and concerns.87 Federally appointed judges, in contrast, were seen as more likely to apply the formal letter of the law and to favor national over local interests. Of course, others favored the more uniform and impartial justice they believed would come from an active federal judiciary, as well as the more effective enforcement of contract and property claims.88
The omissions and lack of detail in Article III were not simply caused by a desire to avoid difficult issues. They were part of the process of compromise that characterized the drafting of the Constitution.89 The widely divergent views of the Convention delegates regarding federal judicial power were seen as best handled, not by a contentious vote that created triumphant winners and disgruntled losers, but by a process of “instrumental reason”90 that sought compromise through agreement on general principles and deferral of contentious issues with immediate political consequences.91 Such deferrals were also seen as better constitutional craft, since constitutions were envisioned as declarations of broad general principle that should not get bogged down in details better handled through ordinary political processes.92 Finally, as practical politicians, the Founders also knew that they needed to get the new Constitution ratified, and that the structure and powers of a federal judiciary were likely to be a major issue in the coming debates.93 It was better to leave those subjects somewhat vague and unresolved than to specify one particular position that would create a clear target for antiratification sentiment.
The result was compromise through ambiguity, both with respect to the provisions actually included in the Constitution and in what was omitted. This lack of detail was certainly noted at the time.94 Indeed, many of the objections to the Constitution as drafted in 1787 were to the lack of detail regarding the judicial powers and the possibilities it created for an “oppressive” federal judiciary.95 Many of the calls for a Bill of Rights were to safeguard traditional judicial procedures in both criminal and civil trials.96 The result was a widely held contemporary perception of ambiguity and confusion regarding the meaning and scope of the constitutional provisions relating to the federal judiciary.97
In the Federalist Papers, James Madison and Alexander Hamilton, while defending specific constitutional provisions regarding the judiciary, never claim that the Constitution actually defines the precise relationship between legislative and judicial power or details what “judicial power” it has granted to the judicial branch. In Federalist 47, Madison, citing Montesquieu, defends the general concepts of separation of powers and judicial independence. He states that there is a danger to liberty “if the power of judging be not separated from the legislative and executive powers.”98 Madison goes on to assure his audience that this danger is only posed when one branch of government is completely joined with or subservient to another. He presents many instances in the British and American state constitutions where the various branches of government interact, check, and balance one another. A critical aspect of such arrangements, he says, is that “[t]he entire legislature can perform no judiciary act.”99 He does not tell us what constitutes a “judiciary act,” or what powers are included under the “power of judging.”100 He does not mention contemporary concerns over jury trial rights, equitable powers, and appellate review of factual findings. Nor does he state whether the powers traditionally asserted as inherent judicial authority over court procedures, discipline, and sanctions are part of that federal power.
Hamilton, in Federalist 78, implicitly responds to the fears of an oppressive federal judiciary by making his famous argument that it is the “least dangerous branch” having neither the power of the sword, nor of the purse, nor even the power to enforce its own orders.101 Having said that, however, he goes on to discuss the benefits that come from having a strong, independent judicial branch, primarily the constraint it can exercise on Congress to keep it from enacting unconstitutional laws. He talks about “[t]he complete independence of the courts of justice” as an essential element in safeguarding the limited powers granted to the federal government under the Constitution.102 Yet when describing the provisions in the Constitution that ensure that complete independence, he cites only the one expressly stated: the lifetime tenure of federal judges during “good behavior.”103 No other express guarantees of judicial independence can be found in the Constitution, nor any other provisions designed to safeguard it.104 While emphasizing its structural independence, Hamilton never explains how the “least dangerous branch” will be able to maintain its political independence against the more powerful legislative and executive, or even whether such political independence was necessary or desirable.105 The actions of the newly created government would begin to provide some answers to these questions.
B. The First Congress Clarifies Some Issues but Not Others
The Federal Judiciary Act of 1789106 was passed in the first session of Congress. It created the federal court system and set forth its initial structure, which included provisions for trial as well as inferior appellate courts.107 The Act defined and limited the subject matter jurisdiction of the Supreme Court and lower federal courts. It also dealt extensively with the procedures and substantive law to be applied in the newly created courts.108 Most significantly for our purposes, it contained provisions conferring on the federal courts powers that had traditionally been thought of as part of English courts’ inherent judicial authority, including the power to punish contempts and to establish “all necessary rules” for the conduct of court business.109
Many of the provisions of the Act expressly preserved and protected traditional judicial practices like jury trials and limits on appellate review of factual findings.110 While there were some procedural innovations, particularly with regard to evidentiary matters,111 there was greater emphasis on limiting federal judicial power in areas such as subject matter jurisdiction and appellate review of factual findings and interference with jury rights. With respect to the power to punish contempts and establish court rules, the Act essentially granted the federal courts power to keep doing what courts had traditionally done.112
Any legislative act is an implicit assertion of constitutional lawmaking power. In that sense, the Judiciary Act can be viewed as a broad assertion by Congress of constitutional power to regulate the judicial branch. Yet viewed politically with reference to its actual substantive provisions, the Act seems primarily designed to reassure the public, particularly those concerned about the potential powers of the newly created federal judiciary, that these courts would operate in pretty much the same way as the existing state courts, particularly with regard to property rights and debtor-creditor issues.113 Congress was responding to widespread political concerns, raised during the ratification debates, that federal courts might usurp state court powers or abrogate traditional rights safeguarded by state courts. If the Constitution was a compromise that nonetheless moved the country decisively toward a stronger federal government, the Judiciary Act, also a compromise, primarily moved the new government in the opposite direction, toward greater limits and constraints on federal judicial power.114
While scholars have analyzed the provisions of the Act for evidence of constitutional meaning,115 historical work suggests that constitutional concerns were not foremost on the minds of the drafters. They were responding to specific political pressures and concerns, particularly affecting the property rights of various constituents.116 Indeed, the records of the congressional debates over the Judiciary Act reveal a willingness to skirt, if not actually defy, express constitutional provisions.117 Certainly, Congress did not seem overly concerned with tailoring the new law to stay within the clear boundaries of constitutionality, nor to necessarily conform to the traditional powers exercised by English courts.118 The Act does contain express grants of power to the lower federal courts with respect to contempt and rulemaking authority, but it is difficult to say how much constitutional authority may be implied from a law that grants an independent branch of government the power to do something that under traditional understandings of judicial power it already had the power to do. While it might be seen as an assertion of legislative control, it might also reflect a recognition by Congress that in these areas it was approaching a constitutional boundary, and that its power to change the status quo regarding contempt procedure or court rulemaking was limited by separation-of-powers concerns. Most likely, it simply reflected a political need to show both the courts and the public that Congress had no desire to change traditional practices in these areas.119 The Supreme Court would declare, a few decades later, that whatever the purpose of the Act, it was not needed to confer powers the courts already possessed by virtue of their inherent authority.
Nonetheless, Section 17 of the Act reflected the fact that powers traditionally exercised by courts under their inherent authority were potential subjects of controversy between the legislative and judicial powers, controversies where conflicts and difficult constitutional issues could easily arise.
III. Inherent Judicial Authority in the Supreme Court
A. 1790–1865: Declarations and Deference Regarding the Scope of Inherent Judicial Authority
The Supreme Court held its first session in 1790. The Justices were undoubtedly aware that one important task before them was to define the proper role of federal courts both with respect to the other branches of the federal government and the states.120 Some of the contradictions regarding inherent judicial authority can be seen developing in this early period. On constitutional issues, there is a dichotomy between the Court’s rhetoric, which strongly asserts the existence of essential inherent judicial powers derived from the very creation of a federal judiciary, and the Court’s holdings, which are uniformly deferential to and uphold legislation that seeks to limit or regulate judicial power. Another line of cases, based on a court’s traditional common law and equitable powers, recognizes courts’ authority to control their own practices and procedures, while acknowledging that such rules can be legislatively altered.
1. Contrasting Responses to Legislative Limits on Jurisdiction and Sanctioning Power
The early Supreme Court decisions draw a sharp distinction between the federal courts’ subject matter jurisdiction, which they hold is under almost complete congressional control, and federal courts’ sanctioning powers, which are declared to be “necessary” and “essential” to all courts, strongly implying that they are constitutionally required. The Court seems eager to make these broad assertions of inherent judicial authority, since it includes them as dicta in the cases that uphold legislative limitations on subject matter jurisdiction.
Turner v. Bank of North America1214 U.S. (4 Dall.) 8 (1799). Turner was a suit over a promissory note. Id. at 9. The plaintiff and assignee of the note were citizens of different states assigned to a bank, but the plaintiff failed to allege the citizenship of the assignor. Id. at 10. Such an allegation was expressly required under the Judiciary Act, probably to allay popular concern that creditors, by subsequent assignment of such notes, could assure a federal forum for their claims. The plaintiff contended that since this was a suit between citizens of different states, the lower courts had jurisdiction directly conferred by Article III. Id. at 9. involved a constitutional challenge to Judiciary Act provisions that imposed limitations on federal subject matter jurisdiction not present in Article III itself. Justice Ellsworth rejected the argument that “federal [c]ourts derive their judicial power immediately from the constitution.”122 Justice Ellsworth described the lower federal courts as courts of limited jurisdiction entitled to no presumption in favor of their exercise of judicial power.123 In a frequently quoted concurring statement, Justice Chase observed that “the political truth is, that the disposal of the judicial power, (except in a few specified instances) belongs to congress.”124 This characterization of plenary legislative power as a “political truth” suggests that the Court was aware of the institutional context125 in which decisions regarding the power of federal courts were being made.126
In United States v. Hudson & Goodwin,127 unlike Turner, no jurisdictional statute was involved. The question was whether common law criminal jurisdiction could be implied solely from Article III. The Court answered that question in the negative,128 noting again that the jurisdiction of lower federal courts, like their creation, is subject to plenary congressional power.129
Justice Johnson ends the opinion, however, by asserting that certain other judicial powers may be implied—those that are “necessary to the exercise of all others.”130 The examples he gives are all sanctioning powers, and his description of them strongly indicates that they are of constitutional dimension.131 We can see in Hudson, therefore, the beginning of the Court’s studied ambiguity regarding inherent judicial power. The Justices seem eager to declare the existence of such powers, particularly those necessary to maintain decorum and order in their courts. Yet their assertion is purely theoretical, made in a case to which it is only marginally relevant. Moreover, while these powers appear to be derived from constitutionally granted power, the extent to which they may be limited or restricted by Congress is not discussed.132
Nine years later, Anderson v. Dunn13319 U.S. (6 Wheat.) 204 (1821). presented the Court with another opportunity to discuss judicial contempt power even though the case actually involved the validity of congressional power to punish nonmembers for contempt.134 Since there was no statute or constitutional provision expressly conferring such power,135 the question was whether it could be judicially implied.136 The Court held that it could, based on the necessity for “public functionaries” to preserve “the safety of the people.”137 Justice Johnson then cited a similar concept of necessity to explain and justify the judicial contempt power:
On this principle it is, that Courts of justice are universally acknowledged to be vested, by their very creation, with power to impose silence, respect, and decorum, in their presence, and submission to their lawful mandates, and, as a corollary to this proposition, to preserve themselves and their officers from the approach and insults of pollution.138
Having described these powers as universally acknowledged, Justice Johnson seeks to explain why Congress also expressly conferred those powers in the Judiciary Act. He does so somewhat tentatively, suggesting that the statutory provisions might be “an instance of abundant caution” or possibly “a legislative declaration, that the power of punishing for contempt shall not extend beyond its known and acknowledged limits of fine and imprisonment.”139 This suggests that Congress does have some ability to regulate judicial exercise of the contempt power, but also makes it clear that legislation was not needed to confer these powers.
After recognizing the implied power of Congress to punish contempt, Justice Johnson warns against too broad an exercise of such powers. He states that “the genius and spirit of our institutions are hostile to the exercise of implied powers,”140 that an implied power “asserted on the plea of necessity” may be “too broad, and the result too indefinite,” and that “[t]his is unquestionably an evil to be guarded against.”141 He concludes that the congressional power to punish contempt must be inherently limited to “the least possible power adequate to the end proposed.”142 Anderson thus introduced into the jurisprudence of inherent power the concept that such powers, while necessary, were potentially dangerous and required reasonable judicial or legislative restrictions on their use.
The constitutional limits of congressional power over contempt were to be tested by a new more restrictive law passed in 1831.143 The precipitating cause was a controversial case in which an attorney was judicially punished for criticizing a judge in a letter to the local newspaper.144 Within a year, Congress had passed a new law substantially limiting judicial use of the contempt power to punish actions taken outside the presence of the court.145 The validity of that new law would not be considered by the Supreme Court for forty-five years.
2. Judge-Made Rules for the Conduct of Practice and Procedure
Like the contempt power, the power of courts to make rules to govern their own practice and procedure was a traditional inherent power of English courts.146 It had also expressly been conferred on the lower federal courts by the Judiciary Act.147 Early cases involving that power, however, arose in a very different context. Procedural rulemaking authority was seen as part of traditional judicial power to apply judge-made legal principles at common law and equity.148 Such powers were subject to legislative revision and were exercised interstitially in the absence of, or pursuant to, express legislation. Most of the issues that arose in cases related to the continuing national controversy over whether federal courts should generally conform to state and local law or be able to develop a separate and uniform body of federal judge-made law.149 Accordingly, these cases tend to involve choice-of-law and federalism issues rather than constitutional questions regarding separation of powers.
Matters were further complicated by the way lawyers at that time understood (and frequently blurred) the distinctions between substantive, procedural, and remedial law, and between common law and equity.150 Broadly speaking, during this period the federal courts were obligated to apply state or local law151 in most actions at common law, including state law rules of practice and procedure. Most of this structure was created by a series of frequently amended federal statutes, notably the Judiciary Act152 and various Process Acts.153 With respect to equitable actions, the federal courts had greater leeway to develop uniform judge-made law, and after 1822, also applied uniform rules of equity practice promulgated by the Supreme Court.154
While the early Supreme Court cases upholding federal judicial authority to deviate from state law practice mostly rely on close reading of these statutes, one can also discern a recognition, perhaps even insistence, that in the conduct of judicial business there are some matters that neither statutes nor uniform rules can control. In such matters, judicial rulemaking is permitted and may even be required. Although the scope of federal power to apply such judge-made rules has waxed and waned, this discretionary procedural rulemaking power has remained and eventually came to be seen as part of inherent judicial authority.
In Wayman v. Southard,155 Justice Marshall sought to make sense of the confusing rules governing choice of law for common law claims in federal court. That case, one of many that grew out of the economic crisis generated by the Panic of 1819, involved the law to be followed in executing a judgment by a federal circuit court in Kentucky. Kentucky at that time had adopted debtor-friendly laws that provided for stays of executions of judgments and doubled the length of those stays if creditors demanded payment in hard currency rather than notes of the Bank of Kentucky. Plaintiffs had sought to quash the execution, which had been made under that Kentucky law, and sought execution of the judgment in accordance with federal law.156
After extensive analysis of the relevant federal statutes, Justice Marshall concludes that the actions of the court officers in executing the judgment were a “mode of proceeding” under the Permanent Process Act of 1792. He held that the Act only required adherence to state procedures in effect in 1789157 and permitted the federal courts to make alterations and additions to such practices in any event. Accordingly, Kentucky federal courts had no obligation to apply current Kentucky law to the execution of the judgments.158
Marshall spends a great deal of the opinion analyzing and ultimately rejecting the defendants’ argument that Congress could not constitutionally delegate to federal courts the power to alter modes of proceeding in suits at common law.159 He notes that not all such delegations of legislative power are valid, and that much depends on the importance of the subject being regulated and the scope of the discretionary power granted.160 He holds that the delegation of rulemaking power in the Process Act is permitted because it is directed at discretionary decisions regarding ministerial matters, within the broad directions of the statute.161
Marshall then shifts ground to defend the delegation on a slightly different basis. He acknowledges that whether to permit the execution sale for notes or specie is a “more important exercise of the power of regulating the conduct of the officer” but concludes that it is “of the same principle.”162 He also states that “[a] general superintendence over this subject seems to be properly within the judicial province, and has been always so considered.”163 He does not use the terms “inherent” or “implied” but describes it as a traditional power of common law courts. In short, delegation of rulemaking power was appropriate because courts already possessed that power, at least potentially.
Some of Marshall’s arguments in favor of delegation seem to anticipate those later used to justify procedural common law. It is a discretionary power to “vary minor regulations,” which enables the courts to respond to changed circumstances.164 Moreover, it operates at the level of specificity where the legislative and judicial functions overlap.165 Similar arguments would be used to justify an inherent power of courts to develop interstitial practice rules in the absence of legislation.
Bank of United States v. Halstead16623 U.S. (10 Wheat.) 51 (1825). was a companion to Wayman that also involved a federal execution challenged as inconsistent with Kentucky state law.167 Justice Thompson, following Wayman, also asserted the validity of the Process Act’s delegation of power to federal courts to alter state law modes of proceeding. He went on to note that power to control the execution of its judgments “is a power incident to every Court from which process issues.”168 He saw it as based on common law rather than constitutional power, however, since he also noted that if misused, such judge-made procedures could be readily corrected by legislation or rules made by the Supreme Court.169
3. Cary v. Curtis: The End of Inherent Judicial Authority?
The strange and obscure case of Cary v. Curtis17044 U.S. (3 How.) 236 (1845). contains the most complete denial of inherent judicial authority found in any Supreme Court case, as well as dissents that contain some of its most ringing affirmations. It involved an 1839 statute requiring customs collectors to pay all taxes they collected into the Treasury, including those paid under protest.171 The majority, applying private law principles, held that the statute was a bar to plaintiff’s action against the New York customs collector for money paid under protest.172 Because the federal government had sovereign immunity, it was unclear in light of this decision whether individuals retained any right to bring judicial actions for wrongful tax assessments, an issue the majority expressly refused to reach.173
The statute could therefore be seen as depriving courts of the core constitutional power of adjudication.174 This was the conclusion reached by Justice Story, one of two dissenters, who attacked the majority’s interpretation as unconstitutional. He stated: “[T]he judicial power, designed by the Constitution to be the final and appellate jurisdiction to interpret our laws, is superseded [by the majority’s opinion] in its most vital and important functions.”175 Justice Daniel, for the majority, asserted that the “judicial power of the United States, although it has its origin in the Constitution, is (except in enumerated instances, applicable exclusively to this Court) dependent for its distribution and organization, and for the modes of its exercise, entirely upon the action of Congress.”176
If the majority’s statement in Cary v. Curtis had become the dominant view, it is hard to see how any concept of a core constitutional adjudicative power inherent in the courts would have survived. However, the foreclosure of rights to judicial redress, which the dissenters feared, was never actually endorsed by the majority,177 and the issue became moot when thirty-six days later, Congress passed additional legislation clarifying that the right to sue collectors for disputed customs duties had not been eliminated.178
The question remains, of course, why a majority of the Court had been willing to endorse such an absolute statement of legislative power over the judiciary. It is possible the majority truly believed that the Constitution gave Congress plenary power over all aspects of the federal judiciary, except for the small number of cases entrusted to the original jurisdiction of the Supreme Court. It is also possible that the Court was simply unwilling to challenge Congress on a matter so clearly affecting the relative powers of the legislative and judicial branches. Yet the subsequent history of the cases suggests a third intriguing alternative—that the Court’s seeming acquiescence in congressional supremacy may have been strategic. By noting the ambiguities raised by the Act, but by refusing to hold even the most extreme interpretation unconstitutional, the Court placed full responsibility on Congress for potentially depriving citizens of any right of redress against corrupt or incompetent customs inspectors. The alacrity with which the statute was clarified indicates that this political judgment was likely correct.
It also suggests a reason beyond mere temerity why, in cases like Hudson and Anderson, the Court asserts the existence of an essential, constitutionally based inherent power that it never actually exercises. If, by such repeated assertions, it can convince members of Congress and the public that there are such constitutionally based powers, but their scope is uncertain and Congress has primary responsibility for defining and keeping them within reasonable limits, that may actually provide greater safeguards for judicial independence than a more strident and possibly unenforceable assertion of judicial power. In any event, Cary v. Curtis represents one instance of extreme reluctance to assert constitutionally based inherent judicial power.
B. 1865–1918: The Court Expands Inherent Authority in Problematic Ways
The post–Civil War period saw a growing trend toward professionalization and codification of the law as legal “science.”179 Judges saw themselves as possessing unique technical expertise derived from the accumulated wisdom of the common law. It is not surprising that during this period the Supreme Court also sought to assert greater power and independence on behalf of the lower federal courts. Such growing assertiveness wielded by primarily conservative judges in a nation undergoing rapid political and economic change led to broad and controversial decisions. Some of these were based on far-reaching constitutional principles like substantive due process;180 others relied primarily on interpretive principles and narrow reading of statutes that left more room for judicial autonomy and application of judge-made equity and common law.181
The tendency to interpret common law principles broadly and statutes narrowly can be seen in many of the cases from this period involving inherent judicial power. The limits on contempt power in the 1831 statute were held constitutional, but later cases nevertheless expanded that power to virtually any public statements judges found insulting or obstructive.182 With respect to procedural rulemaking, the Conformity Act of 1872 theoretically mandated federal adherence to state court practice, but the statute was so vaguely written and subject to so many exceptions that it seems to have actually encouraged development of separate federal procedures. Many judge-made procedural rules, even some directly contrary to state statutes, were justified as applications of traditional common law, equity, or inherent powers.183 By the end of this period there were increasing calls for judicial reform, including new rules to govern federal procedure.
1. Contempt and Other Sanctions
Ex parte Robinson18486 U.S. (19 Wall.) 505 (1873). upheld the constitutionality of the 1831 statute, limiting judicial power to punish contempt, but still managed to expand the federal courts’ inherent sanctioning authority. Robinson, an attorney, had been held in contempt and “disbarred from further practice in the court.”185 Robinson argued that disbarment was not a permitted punishment for contempt under the 1831 statute.
Justice Field, writing for the majority, made two contradictory statements about the contempt power (or perhaps a single ambiguous one). He reaffirmed its “essential” and indefeasible nature,186 yet stated that since Congress has plenary power over the jurisdiction of lower federal courts, their “powers and duties” were wholly dependent on legislative action.187 The juxtaposition of these two statements is confusing but may be seen as dicta since the statute did not completely abrogate this essential power but merely sought to limit its use to certain specific situations. Justice Field had no difficulty affirming the validity of the statute and the limits it set as constitutionally permitted regulation of contempt proceedings. However, he went on to hold that even though disbarment was not a punishment for contempt under the statute, it could nonetheless be imposed under the court’s inherent authority, thereby effectively undercutting the restrictive purpose of the legislation.188
In Ex parte Robinson, the Court accepted legislative limitations on sanctioning powers it had just described as necessary and essential to all courts. It followed that by declaring that another power, disbarment, was also inherent and available to courts without any statutory authorization. It did not state whether the power to admit and disbar attorneys was “essential” or constitutionally required. The overall effect was to expand judicial independence and sanctioning power, but not in a particularly clear or coherent way.
Other cases further developed the legal standards applicable to proceedings for contempt and disbarment. Some dealt with the question of whether disbarment, if imposed without all the protections of a criminal trial, satisfied due process.189 Others considered the types of orders that, if violated, could justify punishment by contempt.190 Still, others construed the contempt statute itself to determine whether various forms of conduct fell within its scope.191
In two controversial cases decided toward the end of this period, the Court set forth an even broader interpretation of its sanctioning powers. Marshall v. Gordon192243 U.S. 521 (1917). involved a congressional contempt order issued against the U.S. Attorney for the Southern District of New York.193 The issue was whether the order was within Congress’s “ancillary and implied” power to summarily punish contempt.194 The Court held that the contempt power was based “upon [a] right of self-preservation” and could only be used to deter or remedy conduct that interfered with essential legislative functions.195
This concept of contempt orders based on “self-preservation” was dramatically expanded in Toledo Newspaper Co. v. United States.196 The Toledo Newspaper case involved a judicial contempt order against an Ohio newspaper that had published material critical of the judge’s actions in a pending case.197 The newspaper appealed on the ground that its allegedly contemptuous conduct did not take place in or near a courtroom.198 The 1831 statute prohibited summary punishment for contempt cases “except the misbehavior of any person in [the court’s] presence, or so near thereto as to obstruct the administration of justice.”199
Chief Justice White, writing for the majority, held the statute to be merely declarative of the court’s preexisting inherent authority.200 Relying on the concept of self-preservation expounded in Marshall, he concluded, “The test, therefore, is the character of the act done and its direct tendency to prevent and obstruct the discharge of judicial duty.”201 Finding the evidence sufficient to demonstrate such obstruction, the majority affirmed the contempt order.202 Justice Holmes wrote a famous dissent, which relied both on the language of the statute and the need for judges to show some “firmness of character” in the face of criticism.203
In Toledo Newspaper, the Supreme Court’s tendency to construe federal statutes narrowly to provide room for judicial discretion was taken to a troubling extreme. The words of the statute were virtually ignored in favor of a hypothetical, broad, and probably fictitious common law power of contempt.204 The case was controversial and severely criticized for creating a new doctrine of contempt by publication.205
2. Power over Practice and Procedure
By the mid-nineteenth century, some states had moved away from common law pleading and adopted new “codes” that merged common law and equity practices.206 The federal courts, however, maintained separate forms of action for law and equity. In 1872, Congress passed the Conformity Act,207 which substituted a “dynamic” principle of conformity to state practices for the older “static” rule embodied in the Process Acts. But the conformity required was a loose one, subject to broad and easily invoked exceptions. State practices themselves were frequently unclear or variable.208 Moreover, expansion of general federal common law and the tendency to view procedure as a technical subject of primary interest to the legal profession gave federal judges substantial freedom to develop and apply their own preferred procedures.209
Nudd v. Burrows21091 U.S. 426 (1875). illustrates the Supreme Court’s receptivity to such judicial procedural freedom. The federal judge in a jury trial had commented on the evidence and refused to allow the jury to take his written instructions and evidence into the jury room. Both of these actions violated express provisions of the Illinois Practice Act, and therefore, the appellant argued, required reversal under the Conformity Act. The Supreme Court disagreed. Justice Swayne explained that with the advent of code pleading, substantial disparities were created between the procedural rules in many states, and common law pleading should still be followed in the federal courts. The Conformity Act, in his view, was designed for the benefit of lawyers, who would otherwise have the burden “of studying two distinct systems of remedial law, and of practising according to the wholly dissimilar requirements of both.”211 The “personal administration” of a judge’s duties on the bench were not intended to be affected by the Act, and if they were, the “powers of the judge” under the common law would be “largely trenched upon.”212 He concluded that the “personal conduct and administration of the judge” was neither a “practice, pleading, nor a form nor mode of proceeding” under the Act, and it did not have to conform to state law.213
Nudd interpreted the Conformity Act narrowly to provide substantial freedom for federal judges to follow their own courtroom procedures. The Court employed the same interpretive strategy that would be used in later years to justify procedural innovations that were seemingly inconsistent with existing statutes or general rules.214 One other notable feature of Nudd is the Court’s assertion about the purpose of the Conformity Act, which illustrates the tendency to view matters of procedure as primarily of interest to the legal profession.
Indianapolis & St. Louis Railroad Co. v. Horst21593 U.S. 291 (1876). used the Nudd precedent to justify a federal trial court’s refusal to submit special interrogatories to the jury. Justice Swayne noted with approval the “indefiniteness” of the Conformity Act, which he held permitted federal courts to reject cumbersome state court practices.216 Similar federal judicial authority based on traditional common law or equity practice—or on implied, incidental, or inherent power—was found with respect to power to grant directed verdicts,217 referrals to arbitrators or special masters,218 appointments of auditors,219 and methods of taking appeals.220
3. Legislative Restrictions on Adjudicative Power
No Supreme Court case has ever declared a federal statute unconstitutional on the grounds that it unduly interferes with the exercise of inherent judicial power, but two cases from the mid-nineteenth century did invalidate statutes that were perceived as infringing the courts’ fundamental power of adjudication.
The California Supreme Court made such a ruling in Houston v. Williams22113 Cal. 24 (1859). as a matter of California constitutional law. A California statute required that all appellate courts give reasons for their decisions in writing. A motion to enforce the law in the California Supreme Court was denied by Justice Stephen Field, unsurprisingly, without a written opinion. A concurrence explained that the statute was an unconstitutional “encroachment upon the independence of this department,” which had complete discretion to decide whether to issue written opinions in any particular case.222 While obviously distinguishable from federal separation-of-powers cases,223 it nonetheless demonstrated willingness by nineteenth-century judges to assert their independence and control over the adjudicative process.224
United States v. Klein22580 U.S. (13 Wall.) 128 (1871). is one of the most puzzling cases ever decided by the Supreme Court; it declared a federal statute invalid for exceeding congressional power but did so under unique circumstances that have made its proper interpretation a subject of continuing legal and academic dispute. In 1863, President Lincoln, acting pursuant to a federal statute, issued a proclamation offering a pardon and restoration of property (except slaves) to formerly disloyal citizens who were willing to take and abide by a loyalty oath.226 A subsequent law, passed in 1870, declared that such pardons could not be admitted as evidence in any action against the government in the U.S. Court of Claims, that such pardons would be conclusive proof of participation in the rebellion, and that the Supreme Court would have no jurisdiction to affirm property awards based on such pardons.227
Chief Justice Chase acknowledged that the U.S. Court of Claims was an inferior federal court, and thus “the legislature has complete control over the organization and existence of that court.”228 Yet he held that by prescribing how the federal courts must treat certain evidence and decide certain claims, “Congress has inadvertently passed the limit which separates the legislative from the judicial power.”229 This certainly sounds like a finding that the statute interferes with the core constitutional power of adjudication, but the precise reason it does so remains unclear. Chief Justice Chase said the denial of jurisdiction is problematic because it was “founded solely on the application of a rule of decision.”230 But Congress surely has power to pass laws that become “rules of decision” for the courts, as well as power to prescribe rules of evidence.
Two other features of this case provide narrower bases for understanding the Court’s ruling. By requiring dismissal of particular claims against the United States government in the Supreme Court, Congress was effectively mandating the outcome of cases brought against itself. Chief Justice Chase seemed to have found this a troubling interference with judicial neutrality.231 Second, by removing all effects of the presidential pardon, and treating it, to the contrary, as evidence of rebellion, the statute also seriously infringes on the powers of the executive.232
Klein has had an interesting afterlife. Subsequent Supreme Court cases have tended to construe it narrowly,233 but the case has become a subject of renewed scholarly interest and is seen as raising important questions about the constitutional limits of legislative power over the adjudicative process.234 It also illustrates, as the Court in Klein itself noted, the thin line between legislation and adjudication. Just as judges can legislate through development of common law rules, the legislature may effectively adjudicate if a law it enacts is too specifically aimed at achieving a particular legal result.
C. 1918–1938: Reaction and Calls for Reform
Expansion of judicial authority ultimately led to reaction and calls for reform, powered largely by ideas from the Progressive Movement. Many lawyers, academics, and even some court decisions sought to roll back the more expansive constitutional claims of the Lochner Era to leave room for state and federal legislative reforms. With respect to inherent judicial authority, curbs on the contempt power in the newly enacted Clayton Act were accepted by the Court, although in a grudging and obscure opinion.235
There were also increased calls for procedural reform. Prominent academics and leaders of the bar expressed increasing dissatisfaction with the litigation process.236 It was felt that code pleading had proved inadequate,237 the hodge-podge of federal procedure under the Conformity Act was worse, and too much time was spent litigating unnecessarily complex procedural matters.238 Reformers called for clear, simplified, and uniform rules of practice and argued that judges rather than legislatures should be given primary responsibility for producing them.239
This last point is significant because it illustrates that reformers did not seek to curb judicial power, but rather to redirect it toward what they viewed as more socially beneficial ends. Indeed, inherent judicial authority played an important role in procedural reform proposals. The fact that courts had traditionally exercised independent power to promulgate rules of practice and procedure and that Congress and the Supreme Court had repeatedly recognized such powers gave reformers strong grounds to argue that a broad delegation of power to the judiciary would raise no serious constitutional problems.240 Some even argued that because of inherent authority, no legislative action was needed.241
The advent of legal realism also provided a new and powerful reconception of the judicial role. Judges were seen as lawmakers, not mere interpreters of some “brooding omnipresence” of common law principles.242 Such insights would ultimately contribute to the Erie decision and a new perspective on judicial decision-making.243 The realists did not dislike judges but disliked a certain style of mechanical and formalistic judging. They favored judicial creativity, discretion, and intuition.244 They sought to craft legal rules that were simple, flexible, and responsive to social needs. Some of this thinking would ultimately find its way into the Federal Rules of Civil Procedure.245
The Toledo Newspaper decision remained a source of substantial controversy. Some judges welcomed the opportunity to sanction journalistic criticism they viewed as scurrilous and obstructive of justice.246 Contempt orders similar to the one issued in Toledo Newspaper were issued in at least five other federal cases,247 and they were emulated by state courts in seventeen states.248 Progressives critiqued the decision as both bad law and bad history.249
In 1924, Professors Frankfurter and Landis published one of the first scholarly analyses of the constitutional bases of inherent judicial authority. They strongly argued that Toledo Newspaper had not only misconstrued the 1831 contempt statute but also had misunderstood earlier English law.250 More broadly, it argued that separation of powers was consistent with extensive legislative regulation of the inherent contempt power. The article was also a defense of the constitutionality of a section of the new Clayton Act, which provided that disobedience of court orders issued under that Act was not subject to summary proceedings.251 The Seventh Circuit had already held that, to the extent the statute prohibited summary contempt proceedings, it was unconstitutional.252
The subsequent decision by the Supreme Court, Michaelson v. United States,253 was at best a partial victory for those seeking to justify legislation constraining the judicial federal contempt power. The Seventh Circuit decision was reversed, and the constitutionality of the Act’s provisions were upheld, but only after the Court had narrowly construed the scope of the Act. Justice Sutherland began by noting the Court’s obligation to construe statutes in such a manner as to avoid raising doubts as to their constitutionality.254 He then removed a “grave constitutional question” by interpreting the Clayton Act to apply only to criminal contempt.255 While reaffirming the contempt power as an inherent power of all federal courts that “can neither be abrogated nor rendered practically inoperative,” he acknowledged “[t]hat it may be regulated within limits not precisely defined.”256
The Michaelson decision again demonstrates the costs and benefits of the Court’s schizophrenic approach to inherent judicial power. Once again, the Court asserted the existence of constitutional inherent judicial power, but avoided a direct confrontation with Congress by interpreting its statute as an inoffensive regulation of that power, which raised no serious constitutional problem. To do this, Justice Sutherland treated the right to summarily punish obstructive disobedience as nonessential, in a constitutional sense, while also severely narrowing the scope and effect of the statute. A studied ambiguity regarding which aspects of the inherent contempt power are essential was seen as useful in situations like this, as the Court implicitly recognized.257
Yet Michaelson was also the beginning of a line of cases in which the Supreme Court increasingly distinguished between civil and criminal contempt actions, limiting summary proceedings in the former and requiring more constitutional protections for the latter.258 In accepting and justifying legislative imposition of certain procedural limitations on its inherent authority as reasonable, Michaelson may have made the Court more receptive to reconsidering and imposing further constitutional limitations on its traditional inherent power.259
2. Inherent Judicial Rulemaking Authority
The early 1900s marked the “birth of serious and widespread interest in reform” of judicial administration and court procedures, much of it led by the American Bar Association.260 In the following decades, as proposals for a new uniform code of civil procedure were assessed and debated, two issues arose that implicated inherent judicial rulemaking authority.
The first was constitutional power. The early reform proposals envisioned a relatively short statute setting forth some general principles and delegating power to the Supreme Court (with an advisory committee) to draft the actual rules.261 The basic constitutionality of such delegation seems to have been uncontroversial, largely due to the long history of legislative delegation and judicial assertions of courts’ inherent rulemaking authority.262 Regulation of subject matter jurisdiction263 and substantive law264 were seen as raising more serious constitutional problems and were not included in the delegation. Questions also arose as to whether power could be constitutionally delegated to the Supreme Court to make rules that would supersede existing federal legislation.265
As time went on and the legislation seemed stalled in the Senate, some commentators argued that there was sufficient authority in the judicial branch to promulgate rules of practice and procedure without any legislative authorization whatsoever.266 An even more extreme position, set forth in a piece by Dean Wigmore, argued that it was unconstitutional for the legislature to make any procedural rules.267
The second issue was the level of specificity at which the new rules would be drafted, and whether they would leave room for discretionary judicial rulemaking by individual judges. The reformers sought an end to common law procedural complexity. They wanted simple, flexible rules that would leave judges free to do justice in accordance with the facts.268 The use of federal equity as the basis for the new procedural rules seemed obvious.269 Equity-based rules would provide individual judges with a great deal of discretion in structuring and deciding cases.270 Yet rules are still rules, and one of the justifications for delegating rulemaking to judges was that their greater familiarity with the courts would enable them to create more effective, detailed rules.271 Would the new rules leave any room for inherent judicial rulemaking or would the new rules become a binding code? A 1935 article coauthored by Charles Clark, primary drafter of the new Federal Rules, provides some insight into this question.272 He noted approvingly that prior Supreme Court precedent had placed the “personal conduct and administration of the judge” outside the scope of matters regulated by the Conformity Act.273 He also recognized federal common law procedural rules.274 Of course, none of that insured that judges would retain an independent inherent right to develop and apply practices independent from, if not inconsistent with, the new Federal Rules.275
D. 1938–Present: Procedural Disruption and Innovation
As every law student knows, 1938 was the year federal civil procedure was turned upside down. The newly promulgated Federal Rules merged law and equity and provided relatively clear and flexible procedures for the federal courts. In that same year, Erie Railroad Co. v. Tompkins276304 U.S. 64 (1938). repudiated the concept of general federal common law and replaced it with a new, constitutionally derived obligation to apply substantive state law in all cases except those governed by federal statutory or constitutional law. Since 1938, a great deal of effort by lawyers, judges, and academics has gone into exploring the meaning and implications of those two momentous developments.
The Rules covered some matters, like sanctions for litigation misconduct, that had previously been seen as within the inherent authority of courts. Did the power granted under the Rules preempt that authority? The same question could be raised about inherent judicial authority to make rules governing practice and procedure. Erie had abolished general federal common law but left federal courts free to apply their own rules of practice and procedure. Accordingly, determining the appropriate boundaries between substance and procedure became extremely important and, in some cases, surprisingly difficult. Would Erie concerns and the Federal Rules limit, or perhaps even eliminate, the ability of federal courts to innovate procedurally, to develop new practices and procedures not expressly authorized by the Federal Rules but still comfortably within the scope of “procedure” for Erie purposes?
Eighty years later it is quite clear that the answer has been a resounding “no.” Far from eliminating procedural innovation, the period following 1938 has been a golden age of sorts for the development of federal procedural common law, most of it justified either explicitly or implicitly as exercises of inherent judicial authority. Moreover, the constitutional core of inherent judicial authority has also made a comeback of sorts, as judges and academics confront constitutional questions regarding separation of powers that require them to inquire deeply into the nature of the indefeasible powers granted to the federal judiciary under Article III.
1. Sanctions for Litigation Misconduct
The new Federal Rules of Civil Procedure authorized sanctions for a wide variety of litigation misconduct. Rule 37(b) listed a series of increasingly severe sanctions that could be issued for noncompliance with discovery orders, including default judgment or dismissal of the litigation.277 It also provided that “refusals” to comply with discovery orders could be considered contempt resulting in arrest.278 Other potential sanctions for litigation misconduct could be found in Rule 41(b) and Rule 11.279 It was unclear whether these Rules provided alternatives to sanctions under inherent judicial authority, were a preferred method to be used whenever applicable, or were intended to replace the use of inherent judicial sanctioning authority.280 Also, the Rules provided little guidance as to when particular sanctions could or should be imposed.281
Societe Internationale v. Rogers was one of the first Supreme Court cases to consider these issues.282 Petitioner, a Swiss holding company, had failed to provide banking records ordered pursuant to Rule 34. It claimed it was barred from making such production by Swiss law. Moreover, the Swiss Federal Attorney had constructively “seized” the records, prohibiting their transmission to third persons.283 A special master had found “no proof, or any evidence at all of collusion” with Swiss authorities and that petitioner “ha[d] shown good faith in its efforts (to comply with the production order).”284 The district court, while accepting the findings of the special master, dismissed Societe Internationale’s lawsuit for failure to comply with the court’s document production orders. The judge justified that dismissal on the basis of Rule 37, which he held provided for sanctions even in the absence of “willful” disobedience of court orders.285 He also invoked the court’s “inherent power to dismiss a suit, stay a trial or impose other limitations on the right to proceed.”286
Justice Harlan held that the district court’s power to dismiss with prejudice for noncompliance with the production order depended “exclusively” on Rule 37 and that reliance on inherent judicial authority “can only obscure analysis of the problem before us.”287 He interpreted the sanctioning authority conferred by Rule 37 with reference to the constitutional limitations of due process and concluded that prior cases288 “leave open the question whether Fifth Amendment due process is violated by the striking of a complaint because of a plaintiff’s inability, despite good-faith efforts, to comply with a pretrial production order.”289 He held that in light of due process concerns, “Rule 37 should not be construed to authorize dismissal[s]” when noncompliance is due to “inability, and not to willfulness, bad faith, or any fault of petitioner.”290
After Rogers, it would have been reasonable to conclude that inherent judicial authority was no longer available to federal courts for sanctioning litigation misconduct, at least with respect to procedures regulated under the Federal Rules. This perception would be changed dramatically just four years later with the decision in Link v. Wabash Railroad Co.291 In Link, the plaintiff’s attorney, in a case that had been pending in the district court for six years, failed to attend a scheduled pretrial conference. Two hours after the conference, the district judge, finding that the plaintiff’s attorney had failed to give a “reasonable reason” for not appearing, dismissed the case with prejudice.292 The dismissal order stated that it was an exercise of the court’s inherent power and was based on the “failure of the plaintiff’s counsel to appear at the pretrial, for failure to prosecute this action.”293 The court of appeals affirmed based on the “inherent powers” of courts to dismiss as a sanction for “disregard by parties of orders, rules or settings.”294
The Supreme Court affirmed, but Justice Harlan justified the dismissal not for failure to appear at the pretrial conference but for failure to prosecute.295 He stated that authority to make such dismissals sua sponte was an “inherent power” of “ancient origin.”296 Although Rule 41(b) expressly provided that dismissals for failure to prosecute were to be made by motion, he rejected any implication that the Rule should be read as abrogating that inherent power.297
In Link, Justice Harlan was not only willing to accept inherent judicial authority as providing an alternative sanctioning power to that provided under the Federal Rule, but he also applied an interpretative strategy familiar from earlier cases. Declaring the dismissal power to be a common law rule of ancient origin, he invoked the principle that laws purporting to abrogate such rules should be interpreted narrowly.298
It is impossible to know why Harlan’s views on inherent sanctioning power and its relationship to the Federal Rules appear to have changed so much, yet the difference in the way he presented the issues in the two cases is striking. Rogers focused on the constitutional due process rights of litigants whose motives for failure to comply with discovery may range from nefarious to wholly innocent.299 The Link opinion, in contrast, was largely concerned with matters of judicial administration.300 Harlan expressly noted that loss of the sua sponte dismissal right would make it difficult for district courts to maintain blanket rules for dismissal of “stale cases.”301
Rogers did not quite impose a “bad faith” requirement for dispositive sanctions under Rule 37(b),302 although some later cases seemed to do so.303 An independent line of Supreme Court cases had also recognized a bad faith exception to the American Rule against awarding attorney’s fees as costs.304 This was said to be an inherent power of courts derived from equity practice.305
Accordingly, by the time Chambers v. NASCO306501 U.S. 32 (1991). was being decided, there was little doubt that bad faith litigation misconduct was sufficient to justify a massive award of attorney’s fees. The question was whether inherent judicial authority could be used to justify that sanction when a substantial amount of the misconduct was also subject to sanctions under specific Federal Rules.307 Although Link had shown that inherent authority was available to provide supplemental procedures not stated in the Rules,308 the order in NASCO seemed like a displacement of such authority rather than a supplement. Justice White asserts a right to use inherent authority when the court, exercising its “informed discretion,” concludes that the statute or authority is not “up to the task.”309 This is an assertion not just of inherent authority to supplement gaps in the Rules, but to make judgments as to their adequacy, and to substitute other more effective sanctions. Prior to asserting this power, the Court cited a long string of inherent authority precedents, ambiguously mixing constitutional and nonconstitutional descriptions of the power, and expressly finding “no need” to distinguish between those powers.310 Indeed, as we have seen, the power being asserted in NASCO itself is ambiguous.311 Through this ambiguity, the Court avoids a direct challenge to the legitimacy of federal rulemaking yet preserves a wide judicial freedom of action at a time of growing concerns over court delays and discovery abuse.
Since NASCO, inherent authority has become an established basis for awarding counsel fees as damages in cases involving pervasive litigation misconduct.312
2. Inherent Authority to Regulate Practice and Procedure
Erie prohibited federal courts from applying substantive general common law but left them free to make decisions on procedural matters as part of their inherent authority. This seems to have worked a subtle change in the Court’s approach to reviewing and justifying such exercises of procedural common law. In previous periods, a judicial practice not expressly authorized by statute was often justified as part of traditional common law powers.313 The post-Erie Court was more likely to cite efficiency and reasonableness as grounds to justify procedural practices not authorized by statute or rule.314 The merger of law and equity also gave federal courts discretion to apply equitable doctrines widely, which effectively expanded their inherent powers.315 While many instances of procedural common lawmaking were expressly described as based on inherent power, there were other instances of judicial lawmaking where the source of the courts’ power remains somewhat mysterious.316
In this period, the Supreme Court also decided a considerable number of cases under what it called its “supervisory authority.”317 Academic commentary has generally viewed this as a particular kind of inherent judicial authority over the administration of criminal justice in the lower federal courts.318 It distinguishes between different kinds of inherent authority that might justify different forms of rulemaking, most notably the difference between procedural innovation in adjudicating individual cases and in promulgating rules of practice and procedure.319
Finally, inherent authority has been invoked in a number of constitutional challenges to statutes on separation-of-powers grounds. The only successful such challenges have involved delegations of core adjudicatory power to decisionmakers other than Article III judges.320 There have been other cases, however, in which arguably inherent rulemaking powers were delegated to nonjudicial actors. Mistretta v. United States321488 U.S. 361 (1989). was a constitutional challenge to the law establishing a commission composed of both judges and other criminal law experts to promulgate sentencing guidelines.322 Justice Blackmun, writing for the majority, rejected a number of arguments based on separation of powers. While acknowledging that separation-of-powers principles would invalidate any law that “impermissibly threatens the institutional integrity of the Judicial Branch,” he found no such threat in that case.323 He held that the powers granted under the statute were within the judiciary’s inherent rulemaking authority, and, in that case, could be constitutionally shared with nonjudicial actors.324 Similar separation-of-powers concerns have been the basis for serious academic consideration of whether other statutes, notably the Civil Justice Reform Act, were invalid for impermissibly interfering with the inherent rulemaking powers of the federal judiciary.325 In short, inherent judicial power remains a potential grounds for invalidating legislation on separation-of-powers grounds, despite the fact that there has never been a successful constitutional challenge on that basis.
E. Preliminary Conclusion
The preceding history has demonstrated how the conflation of constitutional inherent judicial authority with procedural common lawmaking has helped maintain substantial independence and procedural discretion for the federal judiciary. By asserting a unified judicial power, conferred (at least in part) by the Constitution and based on “essential” and “necessary” aspects of the judicial role, the Court has been able, simultaneously, to assert the judiciary’s independence while retaining sufficient flexibility to accommodate political concerns and congressional mandates.326
Moreover, treating all procedural rulemaking not expressly authorized by statute as part of that same inherent judicial authority has allowed the federal courts to exercise wide discretion not only over individual ministerial practices, but over important, potentially dispositive matters often verging on the substantive.327 It has enabled the federal courts to transition seamlessly from deciding such matters under general common law to deciding them under an alternative rulemaking power largely independent of the requirements of the Federal Rules.328 And, it has helped keep the concept of an inherent indefeasible constitutional power of adjudication a central feature of both judicial and academic discussions of separation of powers and judicial independence.
It is not all that surprising, therefore, that we have also seen the Court occasionally note with some approval the confusing and flexible scope of the doctrine,329 and to expressly decline the opportunity to clarify it in the case law.330
We may conclude that the ambiguity of inherent judicial authority is not just an inadvertent doctrinal result, but a useful tool in maintaining the independence and efficiency of the judicial branch. It creates a hierarchy of sorts in judicial approaches to statutes or rules that potentially infringe on judicial power to control their own practice and procedure. First, if possible, interpret the statute or rule as sufficiently narrow that it does not interfere with procedural common law rulemaking. If that is not possible, interpret the statute or rule as a limited restriction that modifies, but does not abrogate, an essential and necessary exercise of inherent judicial power. Only if neither of these options is available should the courts consider declaring the statute or rule unconstitutional as abrogating inherent judicial authority. In the final Part, we will see how a similar strategy is being applied by lower federal courts to a controversial new Federal Rule that seeks to limit their inherent authority.
IV. Does Federal Rule 37(e)(2) Supplant Inherent Authority to Sanction Litigation Misconduct?
Some of the most interesting discussions of inherent judicial authority have been written to attack or defend controversial laws that are claimed to infringe such authority.331 An active public controversy adds urgency and a political dimension to an otherwise abstract theoretical issue.332 The hottest contemporary issue regarding inherent judicial power involves Federal Rule 37(e)(2). That Rule, effective as of December 1, 2015, was intended to reduce the costs of “over-preservation,” the frequently expressed concern of corporate defendants333 that existing discovery rules required them to spend millions to prevent the inadvertent destruction of marginally relevant ESI.334 It sought to legislatively overrule a line of cases in which courts, exercising inherent judicial power, had ordered adverse inference jury instructions as a sanction for negligent or grossly negligent ESI destruction.335
Rule 37(e)(2) prohibits a court from ordering such severe sanctions for ESI loss unless the party responsible “acted with the intent to deprive another party of the information’s use in the litigation.”336 If there were ever a procedural rule designed to mandate compliance and prevent supplementation or evasion through use of inherent judicial authority, Rule 37(e)(2) would appear to be it. Unlike Link or Dietz, where the Rules set forth one procedure for obtaining a particular result but did not expressly foreclose others,337 Rule 37(e)(2) expressly forbids courts from imposing the most severe sanctions for discovery abuse on any other basis than the one set forth in the Rule. The advisory committee note states that the Rule “forecloses reliance on inherent authority.”338
The question is how federal courts will respond to a rule that expressly seeks to deprive them of a small but significant part of their inherent sanctioning authority. Yet serious questions remain as to whether Rule 37(e)(2) has actually foreclosed courts from exercising inherent sanctioning authority, even for ESI loss. Some judges and commentators have already questioned whether a Federal Rule can displace inherent judicial authority to sanction litigation misconduct, particularly when that displacement is only expressly stated in an advisory committee note.339 Yet the actual decisions of the lower courts thus far bear a striking similarity to the Supreme Court’s approach to prior statutes, which sought to restrict inherent judicial authority. They have interpreted the Rule narrowly to maintain maximum judicial freedom in borderline cases. They have also construed the Rule as consistent with most prior case law decided under the federal judiciary’s inherent authority. With respect to the constitutional issue itself, however, there is the same disparity we noted in other contexts between judicial rhetoric and judicial rulings. While declaring their inherent power to sanction all forms of litigation misconduct, the lower federal courts have generally avoided issuing any orders directly contrary to the mandate of the Rule that would set up a constitutional challenge to the Rule’s validity. The following discussion looks at recent case law and potential additional strategies by which courts may seek to retain flexibility and discretion in sanctioning authority in light of Rule 37(e).
A. Reading Rule 37(e)(2) Narrowly
Courts have narrowly construed the prohibitions of Rule 37(e)(2) because it is, in fact, quite narrowly drafted.340 Since its enactment, federal courts have continued to exercise inherent power to sanction discovery misconduct involving physical evidence341 and discovery misconduct involving ESI that does not result in actual “loss.”342 Rule 37 has also been held inapplicable when the preservation obligation arises from something other than “anticipation or conduct of litigation.”343 And, the courts remain free to use their inherent powers to order “measures”344 to deal with ESI loss other than the ones specifically limited by Rule 37(e)(2).345
Some courts have gone further however and excluded application of Rule 37(e)(2) to borderline cases. For example, courts have exercised greater sanctioning discretion when, even though ESI loss had occurred, it was not the only litigation misconduct involved. Sanctions in those cases were held to also be available under Rule 37(b) and the court’s inherent authority.346 In effect, the courts seem to be applying interpretive principles to Rule 37(e) similar to those the Supreme Court had applied to prior legislation.347
B. Interpreting Rule 37(e)(2) as Consistent with Prior Case Law
Many courts that did not adopt the Residential Funding standard have construed Rule 37(e)(2) as making no change at all in the relevant law. Some courts (primarily in the Second Circuit) interpret the Rule as imposing a new, more stringent and precise “intent to deprive” requirement for the imposition of severe sanctions.348 Many others, however, have continued to apply culpability standards based on their pre-2015 cases, asserting that Rule 37(e)(2) has not changed those standards.349 Neither the language of the Rule nor the advisory committee report that accompanied it is sufficiently clear to resolve this issue.350
Many courts have interpreted the Rule to minimize its limitations on inherent judicial power. Some have described it as simply a restatement of the “willfulness” or “bad faith” requirement.351 Others have permitted the requisite showing of “intent to deprive” based solely on circumstantial evidence that a party intentionally allowed potentially relevant evidence to be destroyed.352 The sufficiency of such evidence to justify severe sanctions often depends on whether the court applies a “clear and convincing” or “preponderance” standard to the issue of intent, another issue left unresolved by the Rule itself.353
C. Implying Inherent Power to Apply Severe Sanctions Under “Exceptional Circumstances”
Some courts have asserted, albeit in dicta, that Rule 37(e)(2) has no effect whatsoever on their inherent judicial authority and that they retain the power to severely sanction all forms of culpable litigation misconduct, including ESI loss.354 These statements are a powerful indication of the high value federal judges place on the doctrine, and they are reminiscent of the Supreme Court’s rhetorical defense of judicial sanctioning powers. Yet the fact that there have been no lower court cases actually challenging the legality of the Rule suggests that these courts are also following Supreme Court examples in not seeking to provoke a direct constitutional confrontation.
Rather, if courts do refuse to obey the limits of the Rule in individual cases, it is likely they will do so not by declaring the Rule invalid, but by finding potential exceptions not explicitly stated in the Rule.355 Rule 37(f), the predecessor of 37(e)(2), stated that it was inapplicable under “exceptional circumstances.”356 The 2006 advisory committee described the exception as a recognition that “in some circumstances a court should provide remedies to protect an entirely innocent party requesting discovery against serious prejudice arising from the loss of potentially important information.”357 This can be read as a reaffirmation of the courts’ traditional equitable powers both under the Rules and their inherent authority.358 It is unlikely that the drafters of Rule 37(e)(2) intended to deprive courts of the power to make such exceptions when equitable considerations strongly required it.359
A second approach would be to rely on the Supreme Court’s statement in NASCO and assert that inherent authority to issue adverse inference instructions is still available when fairness and effective administration of justice require it and when the Rules “are not up to the task.”360 This does not require an assertion that Rule 37(e)(2) is unconstitutional. Rather, as in NASCO itself, exercise of such power can remain constitutionally ambiguous but nonetheless appropriate when the specific situation has shown the Rules to be inadequate and therefore functionally inapplicable.361 As in NASCO itself, recognizing such a limited exception would reassert the validity of the Rule and its applicability in most cases while avoiding knotty issues about the precise constitutional limits of the court’s inherent powers.362 As a plausible interpretation of the Rule, it is certainly no more of a stretch than the holding in Michaelson that the Clayton Act applied only to criminal contempt, or that the jury recall in Dietz was permitted only in civil cases.363
Recognition of such an exception would permit courts to provide a remedy when the Rule’s prohibition on adverse jury instructions for nonintentional ESI loss creates unfairness to an innocent party. Consider a case in which all relevant ESI regarding plaintiff’s claim has been lost as a result of defendant’s negligent conduct. Although the Rule permits judges to inform the jury of the lost ESI, it does not permit them to instruct the jury that they may draw an adverse inference from such loss. Without such a presumption, the jury, lacking evidence, is unlikely to return a verdict for plaintiff, and the judge might even feel obligated to dismiss the case. In the 2006 advisory committee note, judicial intervention was seen as appropriate when an “entirely innocent party” was injured by an opposing party’s “routine, good-faith operation of an electronic information system.”364 Similar scenarios under Rule 37(e)(2) are even more compelling since the same innocent party may be injured by negligent or grossly negligent conduct of the opponent. Retaining such an exception would conform to prior case law and would not be inconsistent with the scope and intent of the Rule.365
Final Thoughts
Ambiguity and confusion in law are understudied phenomena. This is curious since so much of law is ambiguous and confusing. A serious study of legal ambiguity would go beyond mere condemnation and even beyond the more nuanced distinctions of rules and standards. An examination of the different ways that legal ambiguity can arise, from boundary problems to linguistic imprecision to contradictory purposes, can provide greater insight into the nature of some intractable legal questions and a means of achieving greater understanding of the law.
The puzzle of inherent judicial authority presents a unique and interesting form of legal ambiguity. It could be described as a mere boundary problem, a failure of courts to adequately distinguish between core constitutional powers that federal courts possess under Article III and institutional powers to create federal procedural common law, but this study has shown that it is more than that. The confused mashing together of these two conceptually distinct powers is a technique that enables courts to treat them as a single concept. This has proven useful in maintaining the independence and procedural flexibility of the judicial branch. Linking procedural common lawmaking power with “necessary” and “essential” constitutional powers gives them added rhetorical strength and potency, enough to justify favorable treatment of particular statutory interpretations and questionable procedural innovations. The same linkage also allows the courts to avoid many conflicts with the political branches by accepting as mere “regulation” attempts to limit and guide their sanctioning and rulemaking powers. The explanation for the puzzle of inherent judicial authority may be that its conceptual confusion continues to be outweighed by its political usefulness.