Expanding Homicide Liability for a Parent’s Omission

Earlier this year, Jennifer and James Crumbley were convicted of manslaughter and sentenced to 10-15 years for not stopping their teenage son, Ethan, from killing four students at his high school. This is the first known occurrence of an American prosecutor obtaining a homicide conviction relying on a parental omission—or failure to act—where the victim was not the parent’s own child. Parental omissions historically have only triggered homicide charges if the parent fails to protect their child, not others, from harm. Unlike the general population, parents owe a special duty to their child because they are the ones tasked to oversee the child’s care. The Crumbley verdict has dislodged this longstanding criminal precedent. It has expanded a parent’s common law duty to include protection of the would-be victims of their child’s criminal acts. Recently, Georgia has brought manslaughter charges against the parent of a school shooter under similar circumstances. This Essay provides the first legal assessment of this prosecutorial theory and analyzes the various doctrinal, constitutional, and policy considerations surrounding its use.

Introduction

All criminal homicide prosecutions require an actus reus.1 Actus reus is Latin for the physical or external part of the crime.2 There are two ways a prosecutor can satisfy this requirement: either by proving that the defendant committed a voluntary affirmative act or failed to act when they had a duty to do so.3 A prosecutorial theory of liability relying on an affirmative act requires some conscious bodily movement, such as shooting a gun or stabbing with a knife.4 Criminal prosecutions relying on the theory of an omission with a duty will logically occur less often because they require the defendant to have a special relationship or status with the victim (e.g., parent to child, spouse to spouse, contract based, etc.).5 This Essay discusses the legal implications of the much-publicized People v. Crumbley case, the first time an American prosecutor obtained a manslaughter conviction relying on a parental omission—or failure to act—where the victim was not the parent’s own child.6

The common law parental duty of criminal liability has a long tradition in Anglo-American law.7 Parents legally owe a duty of protection and care to their minor child.8 It is not unusual for prosecutors, in fact, to bring homicide charges if parents fail to protect or help their child and the minor dies because of this omission—no different than if the parents had caused the death by a voluntary act.9 However, this parental duty has not, until now, included an obligation to protect persons who may be physically harmed by their child. This kind of expanded duty has erstwhile only applied to civil cases where the victims are seeking monetary damages from the parents.10 The Crumbley verdict—for better or worse—has blurred the lines between these civil and criminal parental duties.11  

Section I focuses on the history of criminal omissions and the rationale for imposing these kinds of duties. This section explores the doctrinal roots of the parental duty of care and its narrow application. Section II details the Crumbley convictions and analyzes how the prosecutor imported the civil parental duty standard into the criminal context. This Section also briefly discusses the recent Georgia case where prosecutors have brought manslaughter charges against the father of a school shooter under similar circumstances. The Essay concludes by discussing the potential constitutional hurdles and policy issues with deploying this expanded duty in the criminal context.

 

I. The History and Contours of a Parent’s Criminal Duty of Care

A. A Duty Owed to the Victim Based on Special Relationship

The use of an omission with duty as a prosecutorial theory traces its origins to English common law and can be viewed, at least in part, as a transformation of a moral obligation into a legal one.12 One of the most famous English cases, Regina v. Instan, puts it in the following way: “A legal common law duty is nothing else than the enforcing by law of that which is a moral obligation without legal enforcement.”13 In this case, the court affirmed the manslaughter conviction on the theory that the defendant failed in her duty to take care of her sick aunt.14 The duty was based on the fact that the defendant lived with her aunt and that the victim had previously provided for her aunt before becoming ill.15 Other English cases and early American cases similarly construed this duty narrowly and applied it only when there was some special relationship or connection with the victim.16 In People v. Beardsley, a case commonly taught in criminal law courses, the court cites to the American and English Encyclopedia of Law and prescribes the duty as follows:

So one who from domestic relationship, public duty, voluntary choice, or otherwise, has the custody and care of a human being, helpless either from imprisonment, infancy, sickness, age, imbecility, or other incapacity of mind or body is bound to execute the charge with proper diligence, and will be held guilty of manslaughter, if by culpable negligence he lets the helpless creature die.17

In this case, the court overturned the defendant’s manslaughter conviction for failing to aid or help the victim when she died of an overdose.18 It concluded that none of the criteria above were met and so the defendant had no special status with or responsibility for the victim such that he had a legal duty to help.19

Today, courts have distilled these earlier rulings and maxims to certain distinct situations where a duty to help is imposed and failing to do so could result in criminal prosecution for homicide.20 These include where the statute imposes the duty,21 where one stands in a certain relationship to another,22 where one is a landowner with an invitee,23 where one assumed a contractual duty to another,24 where one has voluntarily assumed the care of another and so secludes the helpless person to prevent others from rendering aid,25 and finally where one creates a risk of harm to the putative victim and fails to assist them.26

It is important to note that Anglo-American criminal law does not recognize a general duty to help another person who is in peril.27 In other words, if you come across a stranger who is badly hurt on the street and do not provide aid or help, you cannot be charged for homicide if the person ultimately dies.28 A few jurisdictions, however, have enacted so-called “Bad Samaritan” laws that impose a statutory duty to call the police or otherwise provide minimal help if it is reasonable to do so, but these laws are rarely, if ever, used.29 Moreover, violating these statutes only constitutes a misdemeanor or imposes a fine and thus does not carry the kind of punishment associated with a homicide conviction.30 Legal scholars have debated the validity and effectiveness of a legally mandated general duty to help—much of which is not relevant for my purposes.31 The key takeaway here is that states have historically been reluctant to impose a criminal duty to help or protect unless there is some connection or relationship between the defendant and victim.

B. The Common Law Criminal Parental Duty of Care to Minor Child

The parental duty of care for their minor child is one of the longstanding and paradigmatic common law duties triggering criminal punishment.32 Early English and American cases uniformly highlighted the fact that failing to take care of one’s child can serve as an actus reus for a homicide charge if the omission causes their death.33 As one early case puts it when upholding a parent’s homicide conviction, “[i]t is a plain precept of universal law that young and tender beings should be nurtured and brought up by their parents, and this precept have all nations enforced.”34 This duty does not require the parent to cater to “every trifling complaint with which the child may be afflicted” but rather act reasonably and perform any action that is necessary to keep the child safe from danger.35

Prosecutors have used this common law parental duty in various homicide cases across the country, including where the parent failed to protect their child from physical abuse by others,36 failed to secure necessary medical treatment for their child,37 or failed to provide the child with necessary food and water.38 The shared thread in all these prosecutions is that the parents failed in their duty to protect their child, not others, from harm.

C. Criminal Parental Responsibility Statutes

As noted above, legislation is one way for jurisdictions to expand a common law duty and create distinct crimes based on relevant omissions.39 In the parental context, all fifty states have passed some version of a criminal liability statute that targets parents for their child’s unlawful act.40 These statutes have expanded a parent’s common law duty to include a duty to prevent harm caused by their child.41

The most common parental liability statute—sometimes referred to as contributing to the delinquency of a minor—punishes parents in certain circumstances for failing to prevent their child from engaging in criminal activity.42 The purpose of these statutes is to “induce increased parental control of their children.”43 The parents in these scenarios are not prosecuted for the child’s crime but for their inability to prevent it. For example, “[i]f a child is caught stealing, parents are not charged under a burglary statute, but under a parental liability statute for ‘allowing’ their child to steal. The sentence is not related to the theft, but to the parents’ omission to properly supervise . . . their child.”44 These types of statutes can potentially hold parents responsible for child specific illegal acts, such as truancy or curfew violations, as well as general criminal activity.45 But these stand-alone crimes are rarely used by prosecutors and, even when applicable, are typically only classified as misdemeanors and thus do not carry the prison term or stigma of a homicide conviction.46

Another, newer and potentially more serious, statutory crime of omission enacted by some states punishes a parent who fails to properly secure a gun that may be found by their minor child.47 The sentences for violating this duty can range from a fine to imprisonment depending on whether the child harms or kills someone with the unsecured gun or if the parent is aware of a substantial risk of such harm.48 These kinds of statutory crimes provide an additional tool for prosecutors—albeit one that carries less punishment than a homicide charge—to use against parents who fail to control their child from harming someone else.

II. Importing Civil Parental Duties into the Criminal Context

A. The Crumbley Homicide Convictions

Jennifer and James Crumbley were convicted of four counts of manslaughter for failing to prevent their 15 year-old teenage son, Ethan, from intentionally shooting and killing four students at his high school.49 Michigan’s involuntary manslaughter charge is like other states’ and requires that the defendant caused the victim’s death, by either performing some act or by failing to act, under circumstances that show the defendant was grossly negligent or had a culpable indifference to the safety of others.50                  

The Crumbley prosecutor focused on key omissions made by the parents that led to the students’ deaths: the parents neglected to get their son required mental health treatment, disregarded potential signs of intended violence, failed to properly secure the gun, and, most notably, failed to remove him from school the day of the shooting after school officials raised concerns that morning.51 It is important to note that the evidence also showed that the parents were “grossly negligent” or had reason to be believe their son posed a risk to others.52            

Interestingly, the prosecutor did not also charge the defendants with contributing to the delinquency of a minor, a crime available under Michigan law.53 This may have been strategic. Because a delinquency charge is only a misdemeanor in Michigan, its exclusion foreclosed the jury from finding the parents guilty of this lesser charge and not guilty of manslaughter. By bringing only the manslaughter charge, the jury’s decision was either to find the parents guilty of the homicide or acquit them of any criminal wrongdoing. Michigan also criminalizes a parent’s failure to store a firearm with a minor present, but this law was enacted only recently and could not be used against the Crumbleys.54

B. Expanding the Criminal Common Law Parental Duty

This is the first known occurrence where a prosecutor obtained a conviction of manslaughter relying on a parent’s omission where the victim was not the parent’s own child. A prior Michigan case involving a similar scenario illustrates the precedent setting nature of the instant case.55 In People v. Albers, the defendant was also convicted of involuntary manslaughter when she failed to stop her child from starting a fire that killed another child in the same apartment complex.56 The prosecutor in that case, similarly, relied on an omission with a duty as the key actus reus for the crime.57 However, there was no mention of the defendant violating a parental duty; rather the prosecutor argued that the parent violated a contractual duty between herself and the victim both of whom lived in the same apartment building.58

The Crumbleys did not have a contractual or other special relationship with the victims of the shootings that could justify the imposition of another common law duty. Indeed, the evidence suggested that they did not know the victims at all. 59 The only connection was indirect—through their son. This explains why the government’s theory focused on the parental duty. To support a more expansive interpretation, the prosecutor invoked the parallel, but broader, common law civil parental standard but without labeling it as such.60 In the criminal complaint, the prosecutor recited near verbatim the relevant language from the Restatement (Second) of Torts, which requires parents to “control [their] minor child as to prevent [them] from intentionally harming others.”61 Following the prosecutor’s lead, the trial judge also quoted the civil standard (again, without labeling it) when instructing the jury on the theory of liability: “In Michigan, a parent has a legal duty to exercise reasonable care to control their minor child so as to prevent the minor child from intentionally harming others or prevent the minor child from conducting themselves in a way that creates an unreasonable risk of bodily harm to others.”62

But a violation of this common law parental duty is only supposed to trigger tort liability and civil damages, not criminal sanctions.63 Its purpose, in other words, is to compensate the victims, not punish the parents.64 The families of the Columbine school shooting victims in Colorado, in fact, relied on this civil parental standard to sue the parents of the shooters and ultimately settled for millions.65 This is what makes the Crumbley case such a watershed moment. What typically would have been monetary judgment against the parents has become a prison sentence. It is not clear if the defendants will challenge this theory on appeal but, either way, the door has now opened for prosecutors to target parents for not stopping their children from committing murder.66

In fact, Georgia, in a recent school shooting, has charged the father of the shooter with involuntary manslaughter (among other charges) under what seems to be comparable circumstances.67 While the facts are developing at the time of this Essay, it appears that after learning about possible online threats his son allegedly made, the father still gifted his then 13-year-old son a gun and allowed him to possess it until the son used the weapon to kill his classmates.68 A prosecutor can use these facts to develop a prosecutorial theory along the lines of the Crumbley case. The father similarly failed to properly secure the gun or otherwise stop the shooting even though he knew his son posed a risk to others.69 

C. Constitutional and Policy Considerations

Expanding the common law parental duty in this way could face constitutional and policy hurdles. The constitutional due process clause requires that a defendant only be prosecuted for conduct for which they have fair notice.70 In other words, the defendant should know or be reasonably expected to know that this type of homicide prosecution is possible. The question here is whether a parent can be fairly apprised of the severe consequences of failing to stop their child from killing someone else if there was no pre-existing criminal common law duty or statute supporting this kind of homicide prosecution.71 Based on historical precedent, parents would only seem to be on notice that an omission could lead to homicide charges if a parent’s failure caused their own child’s death.

On the other hand, it may be expected that the parental common law duty in the criminal context would organically expand, particularly to include protection of other minors. Most states already impose a duty—both criminal and civil—on parents to control their child from causing physical harm to others (e.g., contributing to delinquency of minor statutes, failure to properly store a gun legislation, common law civil duty to control).72 It is true that violating this kind of duty currently only triggers civil suits or non-homicide charges. Perhaps, however, it makes sense to separate the specific crime or tort from the underlying duty. While the use of an expanded parental duty in a homicide prosecution is new, the duty itself is not. And since there is nothing novel about using an omission to establish a homicide charge, taken together these facts suggest that parents should be on notice of the potential for this kind of prosecution.

There are also policy considerations at play here. It is telling that the charges arose in the context of a school shooting. Deterring gun violence at schools has been a difficult task.73 This type of theory could give prosecutors a new tool in this fight—going after the parents of underage shooters. One could argue that these parents should be punished for ignoring warning signs that their child was violent.74 That said, perhaps these kinds of prosecutions unfairly blame the parent, particularly when the defendant is a teenager: “[A]s children develop, parental influence increasingly competes with other types of influence such as from peers, the community and popular culture, and, therefore, this approach [of punishing parents] is too simplistic.”75

This expansion also opens the door to wider prosecutions beyond homicide which may or may not be desirable. The parental civil duty is general in nature and, so, its expansion in the criminal context could be used to punish parents who fail to exercise reasonable control when their child assaults or physically hurts someone else.76 Actually, this is what Georgia has done in the aforementioned case against the father of the school shooter; in addition to the homicide charges, the State has also brought eight counts of child cruelty against him to account for the victims who were physically hurt but not killed.77 Since the language in these kinds of criminal statutes makes no reference to school shootings, there is nothing stopping prosecutors from charging parents with them in any setting where a parent fails to stop their child from assaulting or physically hurting someone else.78

Conclusion

The purpose of this Essay is not to resolve the constitutional hurdles or evaluate the various policy considerations but rather highlight the uniqueness of this theory of liability and its potential impact. It remains to be seen whether and how the Georgia prosecutor or other prosecutors will use this strategy and, more importantly, whether appellate courts will approve of this kind of expanded parental duty. Given the continued tragedy of school shootings, this type of prosecution could be a step in the right direction. It may be time for the common law parental duty to evolve to include the protection of other children, not just their own.

 

 


* Professor of Law, DePaul College of Law, A.B. Dartmouth, M.Phil., Cambridge, J.D. Harvard.