The Good, the Bad, and the Ugly Behavior

Shaming is usually referred to as the publication of perceived anti-social or illegal behavior of an individual in order to condemn or humiliate him. It has some virtues: it makes it harder for people to get away with wrongful behavior, and it promotes justice. It also promotes freedom of expression and enables efficient deterrence. By spreading information on the behavior of individuals, shaming encourages one to maintain his reputation and facilitates beneficial transactions. Finally, it helps the public to avoid inefficient services.

Yet shaming raises many problems. Anyone can shame another based on individual, as opposed to universal, values, thus offending certain segments of society just because they are different. Shaming can also insult human dignity disproportionately. When the initiators of shaming are private citizens, as opposed to courts, it is committed without fact-checking or due process and can promote the dissemination of falsehoods. Shaming can also spin out of control and develop into a “lynch mob,” violence, and harassment. Thus, an action that started with an aspiration to promote social order can lead to social turmoil.

Shaming is nothing new—people have been doing it for centuries. But the digital era makes shaming easier. Every person can write a post, publicize inappropriate behavior, and shame others. A post on the internet can travel around the world and be shared by millions of users within seconds. Digital technologies make it difficult to keep shaming under control. Thus, it can spread like wildfire, be taken out of context, and develop into defamation, harassment, cyberbullying, and even mass violence against an individual. It can harm individuals who did not violate norms or sanction individuals disproportionately.

In the digital age, forgetting has become the exception and remembering the rule. Online shaming is not ephemeral and is searchable through a simple Google query. It leaves a trail that follows the individual everywhere.

Should the law provide a relief for online shaming? If so, when and how? This Article addresses these questions and aims to provide answers. It focuses on the shaming of ordinary people who are not public figures and are not corporations. It outlines the phenomenon, and addresses shaming’s virtues and flaws. Then it sets forth a taxonomy of three types of shaming: (1) “good shaming”—shaming that is initiated by the court and carried out according to a judicial decision or recommendation; (2) “bad shaming”—shaming an individual by spreading false defamatory rumors, or shaming that got out of control and evolved into defamation or harassment; and (3) “shaming the ugly behavior”—the shaming of a person by private individuals for violating the law, or norms.

This Article focuses on non-ephemeral online shaming. It examines whether search engines should remove links to search results that contain shaming, and if so, when. The Article focuses on the characteristics of digital dissemination that amplify harm to dignitary interests. It explains that the characteristics of the internet and its influences on online expressions can justify new remedies for dissemination of shaming, beyond the traditional remedies for harm that reach the threshold of criminal or tort law.  

The Article overviews the benefits and shortcoming of the “right to be forgotten.” It demonstrates that the benefits and shortcomings are not equally valid in all circumstances. Following this analysis, the Article argues that a dichotomous perspective that chooses between oblivion and permanent memory is inappropriate. This Article makes the case for a differential right to be forgotten that acknowledges nuances of shaming, which outlines nuanced guidelines for delisting links to search results of shaming expressions, depending on the type of shaming.

INTRODUCTION

A Jewish man refused to divorce his wife for four years, barring her from marrying another, and thus rendering her chained.1 In an unusual move, the Israeli rabbinical court recommended the public to publish his name, photo, and personal details.2 The rabbinical court repeated this practice in another case.3

One day in 2015, a person discovered a defamatory post on Facebook accusing him of racism. Over 6,000 individuals shared the post. Consequently, it went viral and garnered media attention. As a result, he committed suicide.4

An Israeli passenger on a flight to Varna verbally attacked a flight attendant during an argument over the purchase of tax-free chocolate. A video documenting the argument was posted on Facebook and went viral.5

Shaming is not new; it has existed in different cultures for centuries.6 In the past, shaming was especially popular for punishing people who were found guilty of minor crimes.7 These sanctions had a disciplinary effect because societies were composed of close-knit communities in which people knew each other well. This led to humiliation and deterrence of the wrongdoer. This punishment was efficient because of the familiarity of the community with the offender.8 The industrial revolution changed the community. Rapid urbanization allowed people to escape from the sting of shame. Consequently, shaming became less effective. In addition, people started to perceive shaming as too brutal a punishment, and prisons provided an alternative means of castigation.9

Shaming has returned. The internet and technological developments created a new “global village.” In the digital age, the scope of shaming is extensive.10 Modern technology allows anyone to take out a cell phone, snap a photo, upload it, and tag it. People record others by using internet-connected devices, share the information, and shame them. The internet of things (IoT) allows even greater surveillance and social control than ever before, as sensors in physical objects can passively record and transmit information to cloud storage.11 Shaming can spread like wildfire, by word-of-mouth,12 copying and imitating posts of other people,13 or information and reputation cascades that form when individuals follow the statements or actions of their predecessors and do not express their independent opinions.14 When many people forward or share a post, it might spread beyond their own narrow social network in a short time, going viral.15

Information that spreads on the internet can reach traditional media outlets that may contextualize it.16 Furthermore, new technologies, including artificial intelligence (AI) and machine learning, allow contextualization and identification of a shamed individual, thus identifying a person who would otherwise remain anonymous or unknown to the person who first published the post.17 Needless to say, tagging can also be used for shaming.18 As a result, the audience may figure out who is in a picture. Courts are discovering the virtues of shaming and encourage using the internet for shaming individuals who broke the law, thus identifying violators.19 Online shaming is not ephemeral. It stays on the internet and remains accessible and searchable through a simple Google query indefinitely.20 Furthermore, as the information circulates, it tends to become more damaging because people tend to believe statements they are exposed to often.21 In addition, the more times a post is shared, the higher it appears in the list generated by a Google search, and the more users will ascribe it relevance.22 This attracts a greater exposure to the post and leaves a trail that follows the individual everywhere.23 Furthermore, due to the “negativity bias,” individuals tend to ascribe more weight to negative content in comparison to other types of content.24 This may result in extensive harm to the individual, infringe on his autonomy, privacy, and sovereignty,25 and sanction him disproportionally. Digital shaming raises a variety of questions and challenges that policymakers must address, yet it remains under-explored.

This Article focuses on the shaming of “ordinary people” who are not public figures or celebrities26 and are not corporations.27 In particular, it deals with shaming done by third parties.28 Should shaming result in an everlasting “scarlet letter”? Should there be a “right to be forgotten” for individuals who have been shamed? What is the appropriate balance between free speech and autonomy, reputation, and even privacy29 of the shamed individual? This Article deals with these questions and aims to provide answers. It offers a comprehensive framework for applying a right to be forgotten to online shaming posts that can be used by judges and policymakers. Keeping these goals in mind, this Article is divided into five parts.

Part I conceptualizes digital shaming. Due to the special properties of digital dissemination, shaming will be defined broadly as publishing and disseminating speech that causes dignitary harm to a person and humiliates him. This definition is not limited to the traditional definition of shaming. It encompasses, under the umbrella of shaming, different types of expressions. Some of them are forbidden according to the law, while others are legitimate. Yet all the types of speech under the umbrella of shaming result in dignitary harm. Following this conceptualization, the Article explores the virtues and flaws of shaming.

Part II offers a descriptive taxonomy of shaming and identifies three main categories: (1) “good shaming”—when the authority to shame is drawn from the law (following a court order or a judicial recommendation); (2) “bad shaming”—when falsehoods and defamation are published,30 or when harmful content is disseminated without a legitimate purpose and in cases of harassment;31 and (3) “shaming the ugly behavior”—when violation of the law or norms are published.32 This Part argues that the arguments in favor and against shaming do not equally apply for all types of shaming. Furthermore, certain types of shaming are inherently wrong. Re-conceptualizing shaming and mapping central types of shaming allow better understanding of this phenomenon.

Part III explores the legal and extra-legal approaches for confronting negative outcomes of shaming and addresses their limitations.

Part IV explores situations in which the law regulates the removal of certain records from databases. It also overviews the laws in the European Union and the United States on delisting links from search engine results. Following this, it explains that the digital age changed the characteristics of dissemination. It argues that the scope of dissemination, the ability to find information, and the access to information via search engines at a later stage justify a new approach towards protected dignitary interests outside the traditional categories of protected interests in civil and criminal law. It proposes that the law should recognize dignitary harm even when the dissemination is not a tort or a crime. Delisting links to shaming information is an important step in restoring the balance between memory and oblivion in the digital era. Finally, this Part examines normative considerations on the right to be forgotten.

Part V argues that the law should acknowledge different shades of forgetting and not rely on a forgetting-remembering dichotomy. It proposes a nuanced approach towards oblivion and outlines differential guidelines for delisting shaming information.

* * * * *


* Ph.D. (Law); Postdoctoral Fellow, University of Haifa—Faculty of Law, Center of Cyberlaw &Policy; Research Fellow at The Federmann Cyber Security Research Center—Cyber Law Program, Hebrew University; Cheshin Fellow, Hebrew University. I thank Guy Pessach, Re’em Segev, Katya Assaf, Ariel Nevo, Jonathan Lewy, the participants of the Hebrew University’s young scholars’ workshop and the participants of the Annual Private Law Association Conference for comments and the Cheshin Scholarship. Last but not least, I thank Jennifer Pierce, Ilana Kornfeld, and their colleagues on the Cardozo Law Review staff for comments, suggestions, and outstanding editorial work.